In a series of papers, Simon Saunders (arxiv:2103.01366 and
arxiv:2103.03966) offers an extensive argument for the Everettian
interpretation of quantum mechanics. The paper on structure
(arxiv:2103.01366) contains the following paragraph:
"Everett called them branches. It is not hard to see that the connection between amplitudes and Born-rule probability is retained for multiple experiments. The amplitude of each branch, at the end of N experiments, as determined by the unitary evolution alone (together with the initial state), equals the square root of the Born-rule probability for that sequence of outcomes )just multiply together the probabilities for the results taken sequentially). Now consider the superposition of all those branches with the same relative frequency for the "+" outcome; not quite so obviously, the amplitude of this superposition is highly sensitive to the discrepancy, if any, between that relative frequency and the Born rule quantity for the "+" outcomes, the quantity p. Let the discrepancy be eps; then the amplitude falls off exponentially as exp( - N eps^2/kappa), where kappa = 4p(1 - p) and N is, as before, the number of trials. It is the first of a number of quantum Bernoulli theorems, the quantum analogues of the laws of large numbers: the amplitudes of branches with the "wrong" relative frequencies fall off exponentially quickly in the number of trials, in comparison with the amplitudes of Born-rule compliant branches."
This argument was criticized by Adrian Kent (arxiv:0905.0624), but the argument persists, largely because it is central to the Everettians' case that their theory is consistent with the Born rule.
While Kent's criticism still stands, he has made much the same mistake as Saunders. This is to assume that in Everett's picture, each trial is effectively a Bernoulli trial, with a probability of success p. This is not the case. Since every outcome occurs on every Evettian trial, the process cannot be seen as a Bernoulli trial. The crucial point of Saunders' argument hinges on the normal approximation to the Binomial (Bernoulli) distribution as the number of trials becomes large. Since the distribution from Everettian trials is not binomial, this approximation does not hold, and the whole argument collapses.
The essence of a Bernoulli trial is that one outcome occurs with probability p (a 'success'), and other outcomes do not occur. This is in obvious conflict with Everett's approach in which every outcome occurs on every trial.
Bruce
> This is to assume that in Everett's picture, each trial is effectively a Bernoulli trial, with a probability of success p. This is not the case. Since every outcome occurs on every Evettian trial, the process cannot be seen as a Bernoulli trial.
>> You're making an implicit assumption that is usually harmless but not when you're talking about the nature of quantum reality. You are forgetting that a Bernoulli trial is not a Bernoulli trial unless the Bernoulli trial has been OBSERVED. And every observer observes that only two outcomes are possible, the coin lands heads or the coin lands tails. And after many trials all the observers in the Multiverse deduce that the outcome of one trial does not influence the outcome of another trial. And all the observers in the Multiverse also deduce that the probability of heads and the probability of tails remains the same for every trial. And that is exactly what is required for something to be a Bernoulli trial.> Which probability textbook did you get that out of?
>>> This is to assume that in Everett's picture, each trial is effectively a Bernoulli trial, with a probability of success p. This is not the case. Since every outcome occurs on every Evettian trial, the process cannot be seen as a Bernoulli trial.
>> You're making an implicit assumption that is usually harmless but not when you're talking about the nature of quantum reality. You are forgetting that a Bernoulli trial is not a Bernoulli trial unless the Bernoulli trial has been OBSERVED. And every observer observes that only two outcomes are possible, the coin lands heads or the coin lands tails. And after many trials all the observers in the Multiverse deduce that the outcome of one trial does not influence the outcome of another trial. And all the observers in the Multiverse also deduce that the probability of heads and the probability of tails remains the same for every trial. And that is exactly what is required for something to be a Bernoulli trial.
> A Bernoulli trial does not require that the probability of heads and tails be equal.
> But Everett entails that on every trial there will be an equal number of heads and tails across all worlds.
On Sun, Sep 14, 2025 at 6:51 PM Brent Meeker <meeke...@gmail.com> wrote:> But Everett entails that on every trial there will be an equal number of heads and tails across all worlds.
--
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups "Everything List" group.
To unsubscribe from this group and stop receiving emails from it, send an email to everything-li...@googlegroups.com.
To view this discussion visit https://groups.google.com/d/msgid/everything-list/CAFxXSLS7HjMe3HDrEtqUJrFj_%2BM%2BwOG-gNRrTi%3DPATEyqwwF4g%40mail.gmail.com.
It's not a quote. I made it up (when have I ever put words in your mouth?). If there are two possible outcomes Heads and Tails then according to Everett on each trial they both occur, albeit in different "worlds", and hence there will be equal numbers of H's and T's regardless of whether the coin is fair or loaded.
--
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups "Everything List" group.
To unsubscribe from this group and stop receiving emails from it, send an email to everything-li...@googlegroups.com.
To view this discussion visit https://groups.google.com/d/msgid/everything-list/CAFxXSLQMWwQivveA9iSJSpq%2BGKm52o7JtE73TJTHE3FsRQmz%2Bg%40mail.gmail.com.
> John correctly observes that he hasn't proposed branch counting, but requires that the Born rule attach probability weights to branches. But he's wrong that nobody ever proposed branch counting. Even Sean Carroll, an Everettian, discusses differential branching as a way to realize the Born rule.