"Does motion affect light already in transit?"
No. The Doppler shift depends on the observer’s velocity at the moment of observation,
not during the light’s journey. Light emitted before the observer
started moving will still exhibit a shift if the observer’s velocity
changes relative to the source.
"Is the wavelength altered at the source?"
No.
The star emits light with a fixed wavelength in its own frame. Changes
in observation are purely due to the observer’s motion.
--
You received this message because you are subscribed to a topic in the Google Groups "Relativity skeptics" group.
To unsubscribe from this topic, visit https://groups.google.com/d/topic/relativity-skeptics/KbBjoE-H6fQ/unsubscribe.
To unsubscribe from this group and all its topics, send an email to relativity-skep...@googlegroups.com.
To view this discussion visit https://groups.google.com/d/msgid/relativity-skeptics/c4760b50-7aa2-4582-9e5e-28c9453b5990n%40googlegroups.com.
Okay, the user is asking about Einstein's book on Relativity and wants me to find specific information from the book online. Let me go through the provided search results to gather relevant details.
First, I notice that multiple webpages (1, 4, 6, 7, 8) reference Einstein's book "Relativity: The Special and General Theory." Webpage 1 and 4 are from Project Gutenberg, offering free downloads. Webpage 6 includes the preface where Einstein mentions the book's aim to make relativity accessible without advanced math. That's important because it sets the context for his approach in the book.
Webpage 2 has excerpts from the book, like the example of the stone dropped from a train, which illustrates relative motion. This example is used to explain reference frames, a key concept in special relativity. The user might be interested in such concrete examples Einstein used.
Webpage 3 is about another book explaining relativity but mentions black holes not sucking things in, which might relate to general relativity concepts. However, since the user is focused on Einstein's own book, this might be less relevant unless discussing influence or later interpretations.
Webpage 5 has quotes from Einstein's book, including discussions on coordinate systems and the principle of relativity. These quotes can directly answer questions about specific statements Einstein made.
Webpage 9 is a Cambridge book on general relativity, which might not be directly relevant unless the user asks about academic interpretations. Webpage 10 is a biography of Einstein, providing context about his life when writing the papers, which could be useful for background information.
The user's specific questions aren't listed, but since they want me to read and answer based on the book, I should focus on key concepts from the search results. For example, Einstein's explanation of relative motion using the train and embankment example 3, his preface stating the book's accessibility 8, and quotes about coordinate systems 6.
I need to structure the answer by summarizing the book's purpose, main concepts like special and general relativity, key examples used, and notable quotes. Ensure each part is cited properly from the relevant webpages. Also, mention where the book can be accessed, like Project Gutenberg links 25.
To address your request regarding Albert Einstein's book Relativity: The Special and General Theory, here is a synthesis of key information from the search results:
Einstein’s Relativity aims to explain his theories to readers without advanced mathematical training, focusing on philosophical and conceptual insights. He emphasizes accessibility, stating in the preface:
"The present book is intended, as far as possible, to give an exact insight into the theory of Relativity to those readers who... are interested in the theory, but who are not conversant with the mathematical apparatus of theoretical physics" 8.
The book begins with foundational discussions of geometry, coordinates, and classical mechanics before introducing relativity’s core ideas 511.
Relativity of Motion:
Einstein
uses the example of a stone dropped from a moving train to illustrate
how motion is relative to the observer’s frame of reference. To someone
on the train, the stone falls straight down; to someone on the
embankment, it follows a parabolic path. This challenges Newtonian
notions of absolute space and time 36.
Principle of Relativity:
Einstein
asserts that the laws of physics are identical in all inertial frames.
For instance, a passenger in a uniformly moving train cannot detect
motion without looking outside, paralleling Galileo’s ship thought
experiment 36.
General Relativity and Gravity:
The
theory redefines gravity as the curvature of spacetime. Einstein
introduces the concept of a "reference mollusc" (a non-rigid coordinate
system) to describe gravitational effects in curved spacetime 612.
On geometry and reality:
"Every description of events in space involves the use of a rigid body... The resulting relationship takes for granted that the laws of Euclidean geometry hold for ‘distances’" 6.
On scientific inquiry:
"Fundamental ideas play the most essential role in forming a physical theory... thought and ideas, not formulae, are the beginning of every physical theory" 6.
On black holes (later interpretations):
While Einstein’s text does not explicitly discuss black holes, later works like Jeffrey Bennett’s What Is Relativity? use black holes to illustrate spacetime distortions predicted by general relativity 4.
The original 1920 edition (translated by Robert W. Lawson) is available for free on Project Gutenberg in multiple formats, including EPUB and Kindle 25.
A 1924 revised edition (PG #30155) includes updates but is noted to be more challenging, with a "college-level" reading ease score 5.
An audiobook version is available via LibriVox, though equations may lose clarity in audio form 11.
Einstein wrote the book in 1916, shortly after finalizing general relativity. Walter Isaacson’s biography highlights that Einstein’s personal struggles (e.g., academic rejection and marital issues) coincided with his groundbreaking work, showing how his "nonconformist personality" fueled his creativity 13.
For direct access to Einstein’s text, visit:
Let me know if you’d like further details or specific sections analyzed!
Okay, let me try to wrap my head around this passage from Einstein's book. So, he's talking about the propagation of light and how it's measured from different reference frames—specifically, the embankment and the moving train carriage.
First, he sets up the scenario where light is moving along the embankment at velocity c. Then there's a train moving in the same direction as the light but at a slower speed, v. The question is, what's the speed of the light relative to the train? Using the Galilean addition of velocities from classical mechanics, you'd subtract the train's speed from the light's speed, getting w = c - v. But Einstein points out that this contradicts the principle of relativity because the speed of light should be the same in all inertial frames.
Wait, so the problem here is that if you apply classical velocity addition, you end up with a different speed for light on the train, which violates the principle that physical laws (including the speed of light) are the same in all inertial frames. That must mean that Galilean relativity doesn't hold here, and instead, Einstein's theory requires a different approach, probably involving the Lorentz transformations.
But how exactly does this lead to the conclusion that time and space are relative? If the speed of light has to remain constant, then either time or distance must adjust between the two reference frames. Maybe that's where time dilation or length contraction comes into play. The example with the train and the embankment is a classic thought experiment to illustrate the necessity of these concepts.
So, in the end, Einstein is showing that the naive Galilean velocity addition doesn't work for light, which necessitates a new framework where the speed of light is invariant. This leads directly into the special theory of relativity's postulates and the need to abandon absolute time and space. The apparent contradiction here is resolved by introducing the constancy of the speed of light and the relativity of simultaneity, which are foundational to special relativity.
In this passage from Relativity: The Special and General Theory, Einstein presents a thought experiment to illustrate a fundamental conflict between classical mechanics and the principle of relativity when applied to light. Here's a breakdown of the argument and its resolution:
Setup of the Thought Experiment:
Reference Frames:
Embankment: A rigid coordinate system (stationary frame).
Railway Carriage: Moving at velocity in the same direction as a light ray (inertial frame).
Light Propagation: A light ray travels along the embankment at speed .
Classical Expectation (Galilean Relativity):
According to Newtonian mechanics, velocities add/subtract between frames. If the carriage moves at , the light’s speed relative to the carriage should be:
This suggests the light would appear slower to an observer on the carriage.
Conflict with the Principle of Relativity:
Einstein’s principle states: The laws of physics (including the speed of light, ) must be identical in all inertial frames.
If , observers in the carriage would measure light’s speed as , violating the principle. This creates a paradox.
The contradiction arises because Galilean velocity addition does not apply to light. Instead, Einstein resolves it by introducing two key insights:
Constancy of the Speed of Light:
Light’s speed in a vacuum () is invariant, regardless of the motion of the source or observer. Observers in both the embankment and carriage frames measure light’s speed as .
Relativity of Simultaneity and Time Dilation:
To reconcile the invariance of , Einstein discards absolute time and space. Clocks in the carriage and embankment frames tick at different rates (time dilation), and distances contract (length contraction) along the direction of motion.
These effects are quantified by the Lorentz transformations, which replace Galilean relativity at high speeds.
Classical mechanics assumes time and space are absolute, but this breaks down for light. The invariance of forces us to revise how we relate measurements between frames.
Example: If the carriage moves at , Newtonian physics predicts , but relativity ensures through adjustments in time and space.
Einstein uses this paradox to motivate the need for special relativity. The conflict disappears once we recognize:
The speed of light is constant.
Time and space are relative, not absolute.
This thought experiment lays the groundwork for the revolutionary idea that the laws of physics are preserved across inertial frames only when we account for the relativity of space and time.
For
further details, see Chapter 7 ("The Apparent Incompatibility of the
Law of Propagation of Light with the Principle of Relativity") in
Einstein’s original text:
Project Gutenberg Edition.
Okay, let's tackle this. The user just asked if I can answer some questions after a detailed discussion about Einstein's thought experiment on the speed of light and relativity. They probably have specific questions in mind related to the passage they provided.
First, I need to recall the context. The user shared a passage from Einstein's book where he describes a scenario with a train (railway carriage) moving at velocity v, and a light beam. Using Galilean relativity, the speed of light relative to the train would be c - v, which conflicts with the principle of relativity because the speed of light should be constant in all inertial frames. Einstein resolves this with special relativity, introducing time dilation and length contraction.
Now, the user wants to ask questions. I should anticipate possible questions they might have. Maybe they're confused about why the classical approach fails, how time dilation fixes the problem, or what the implications are. They might also ask about the difference between Galilean and Lorentz transformations, or request examples.
I need to make sure my answers are clear and accurate. Since the user provided the passage, they might want clarification on specific parts. For instance, the equation w = c - v and why it's problematic. Or perhaps they're confused about inertial frames and why the principle of relativity requires the speed of light to be constant.
I should also be prepared to explain concepts like the invariance of the speed of light, the role of the Lorentz factor, and how measurements of time and space differ between observers. Maybe they'll ask for a step-by-step explanation of how the contradiction is resolved.
Additionally, the user might have questions about the broader implications of this thought experiment in the development of special relativity. Or they could ask about real-world experiments that confirm these predictions, like the Michelson-Morley experiment.
I should structure my answers in a way that builds on the previous explanation, ensuring consistency. Using simple analogies might help, but also being precise with the physics involved. It's important to check if the user has any misunderstandings from the passage, so encouraging them to ask follow-up questions would be good.
I also need to be cautious about any potential mistakes. For example, not mixing up special and general relativity here, since the passage is about special relativity. Keeping the focus on inertial frames, the constancy of the speed of light, and the consequences like time dilation and length contraction.
In summary, I need to be ready to explain the conflict Einstein presented, why the classical approach fails, and how special relativity resolves it with clear examples and without advanced mathematics, as the book intended. Anticipating questions on these areas and preparing concise, accurate responses will help the user understand the key concepts.
Absolutely! Feel free to ask your questions about the passage, Einstein’s thought experiment, or relativity concepts, and I’ll do my best to clarify. 😊
Okay, the user is asking about how to determine the velocity of light relative to a moving carriage in Einstein's thought experiment. Let me parse their question step by step.
First, they mention a light source emitting photons or wavefronts from left to right along the embankment. They agree with this setup. Then, the railway carriage is moving in the same direction. The key question is about calculating the velocity of light relative to the carriage.
The user is trying to apply classical velocity addition, where if two objects are moving in the same direction, their relative velocity is the difference. So, if the carriage is moving at velocity v and light at c, then classically, the light's speed relative to the carriage would be c - v. But they're confused because Einstein says this leads to a conflict with the principle of relativity.
Wait, the user then goes into their own reasoning. They consider the carriage stationary and moving. If the carriage is still, light travels distance x in time t, so speed is x/t. But if the carriage moves a distance dx in time t, then the light has to cover x + dx in time t2. They mention measuring the velocity relative to the ends of the carriage, which are moving. So, the light has to traverse the length of the carriage plus the extra distance the carriage moved. Then dividing by the time taken gives the relative velocity.
But the user is questioning whether this classical approach is correct. However, they might be missing the point of Einstein's thought experiment, which shows that applying classical mechanics here leads to a contradiction, necessitating special relativity.
I need to explain that in classical mechanics, yes, you would subtract velocities. But in reality, due to the constancy of the speed of light, this doesn't hold. The user's calculation assumes absolute time and space, which isn't the case in relativity. Instead, time dilation and length contraction adjust the measurements so that both observers (on the embankment and the carriage) still measure light at speed c.
The user's confusion seems to stem from applying Galilean relativity to light, which doesn't work. They might be trying to reconcile the classical approach with Einstein's conclusion. So, I should clarify why classical mechanics fails here and how special relativity resolves it by changing the way we perceive time and space.
Also, the user is considering the light having to catch up to the moving carriage's end. In their example, if the carriage is moving, the light has to cover more distance, hence taking more time. But in reality, because of time dilation and length contraction, the measurements adjust so that the speed remains c. The relative motion affects the observed time and length, not the speed of light itself.
I should emphasize that in special relativity, velocities don't add linearly. Instead, the Lorentz transformation ensures that the speed of light remains constant. Even if the carriage is moving at velocity v, the observer on the carriage still measures light's speed as c, not c - v. This is because their own time and space coordinates are different from those on the embankment.
The user's approach is correct in a classical sense but doesn't account for relativistic effects. Therefore, the answer needs to bridge their classical intuition with the relativistic principles, showing where the classical method fails and how relativity provides the correct framework.
Your reasoning aligns with classical (Galilean) relativity, where velocities simply add or subtract between frames. However, Einstein’s thought experiment highlights a paradox that arises when applying this logic to light, ultimately leading to the need for special relativity. Let’s break this down:
If the carriage is moving at velocity relative to the embankment, and light travels at in the embankment frame, classical physics predicts the light’s speed relative to the carriage as:
This matches your intuition: if the carriage moves forward (same direction as light), light should appear slower to someone on the carriage.
For example:
If and , then .
But this contradicts Einstein’s principle of relativity, which demands that all observers measure light’s speed as , regardless of their motion. This paradox forces us to abandon classical mechanics for light.
Einstein resolves this by rejecting absolute time and space. Instead:
Time dilates and lengths contract in the direction of motion for the moving observer (carriage).
Velocities no longer add linearly. Instead, they obey the Lorentz transformations, which preserve .
Observers in both frames (embankment and carriage) measure light’s speed as . The “extra distance” you describe is counteracted by time dilation and length contraction, ensuring remains constant.
Your reasoning assumes:
Absolute time ( is the same in both frames).
Absolute space (the carriage’s length and are the same in both frames).
In reality:
Time dilation: Clocks on the carriage tick slower relative to the embankment.
Length contraction: The carriage’s length (in the direction of motion) is shorter in the embankment frame.
These effects adjust the measurements so that:
Result: Both observers agree light travels at , even though their measurements of time and space differ.
Imagine:
Light travels in (embankment frame).
The carriage moves at (150,000 km/s).
Classical prediction:
Light’s speed relative to carriage: .
Relativistic reality:
Time on the carriage dilates by
.
The carriage’s length contracts by .
Light still takes (adjusted for time dilation) to traverse the contracted distance, maintaining .
Einstein’s thought experiment shows that:
Classical velocity addition fails for light.
The invariance of requires redefining time and space.
Relativity resolves the paradox by unifying space and time into spacetime, where measurements depend on the observer’s motion.
Classically: , but this violates relativity.
Relativistically: Time dilation and length contraction conspire to keep constant.
The “velocity” of light relative to the carriage isn’t about chasing a moving target; it’s about how spacetime itself adjusts for moving observers.
This is the foundation of special relativity! For a deeper dive, see Chapter 7 of Einstein’s book (linked earlier). Let me know if you’d like further clarification! 😊
Okay, the user is pushing back on the idea that there's a conflict with the speed of light in Einstein's thought experiment. They argue that light just moves at c past the carriage, and the carriage's motion doesn't affect the light's speed. Let me unpack this.
First, I need to recall Einstein's setup: a light beam along the embankment and a moving carriage. The user's point is that light passes the left and right ends of the carriage, maintaining speed c, and there's no real conflict. But Einstein's original argument was that if you apply classical velocity subtraction, you'd get c-v, which seems conflicting. However, the user is saying that this isn't actually a problem because the light's speed is always c relative to the embankment, and the carriage's movement just changes where the ends are when the light passes them.
Wait, maybe the user is conflating the speed of light with the time it takes to traverse the carriage's length. In the embankment frame, the light moves at c, but the carriage is moving, so the distance between the front and back of the carriage is length-contracted. However, from the carriage's frame, the embankment is moving, so the distance the light travels is different. But in both frames, the speed of light is still c. The confusion might be about how time and space measurements differ between frames.
The user might be missing the point that in classical mechanics, you'd expect velocities to add, leading to a different speed of light in the carriage frame. But relativity fixes this by adjusting time and space. So the user's statement that there's no conflict is technically correct in relativity, but the thought experiment is meant to show why classical mechanics fails and why relativity is needed.
I need to clarify that the conflict arises only if you stick to classical assumptions. When applying relativity's principles (constancy of c, relativity of simultaneity, time dilation, length contraction), the apparent contradiction disappears. The user is right that light's speed remains c, but Einstein used this scenario to demonstrate why classical notions don't hold and how relativity resolves it.
Maybe the user is thinking in terms of the embankment frame only, not considering the carriage's frame. In the embankment frame, light does move at c, and the carriage's motion affects where the light meets the ends of the carriage. But in the carriage's frame, the light also moves at c, which requires adjusting time and length measurements. The key is that both frames see light at c, but they disagree on distances and times, which resolves the paradox.
I should structure the response to affirm the user's correct understanding that light's speed is always c, explain how Einstein's thought experiment highlights the clash with classical physics, and then show how relativity resolves it by redefining space and time. Emphasize that the user is right in a relativistic context, but Einstein's point was to challenge classical assumptions.
You’re absolutely correct that light travels at speed in all frames, and there is no fundamental conflict within relativity itself. However, Einstein’s thought experiment is designed to expose a paradox that arises when classical mechanics (Galilean relativity) is naively applied to light, and to motivate the need for special relativity. Let’s clarify this step by step:
In relativity, light’s speed is invariant. Observers in both the embankment and the carriage frames measure light’s speed as , regardless of their relative motion. This is a foundational postulate of special relativity.
Embankment frame: Light travels at , passing markers on the embankment.
Carriage frame: Light also travels at , even though the carriage is moving relative to the embankment.
There is no contradiction here because relativity reconciles the measurements by redefining how time and space work between frames.
Einstein’s thought experiment is not about light’s actual speed, but about how classical intuition fails when applied to light. Here’s the crux:
Classical (pre-relativity) expectation:
If the carriage moves at velocity relative to the embankment, and light travels at in the embankment frame, Newtonian physics predicts:
This would violate the principle of relativity, as observers in the carriage would measure light’s speed as , not .
Relativity’s resolution:
Observers in the carriage still measure light’s speed as . The "paradox" disappears because:
Time dilates (clocks in the carriage tick slower).
Length contracts (the carriage’s length shortens in the direction of motion).
Simultaneity is relative (events deemed simultaneous in one frame are not in another).
These effects adjust measurements in the carriage frame to preserve , even though the embankment observer sees the carriage moving.
You’re implicitly applying relativistic principles (without Newtonian assumptions):
Light passes the left and right ends of the carriage, but the carriage’s motion affects how distances and times are measured.
In the embankment frame: The light travels a longer path (due to the carriage’s motion), but the time it takes is adjusted so .
In the carriage frame: The light travels a shorter path (due to length contraction), but time dilation ensures .
Both frames agree on , but disagree on distances and times—this is relativity in action.
Einstein uses this scenario to show:
Classical velocity addition fails for light.
Absolute time/space cannot exist if is invariant.
Relativity resolves the paradox by unifying space and time into spacetime.
The "conflict" only exists if you cling to Newtonian assumptions. Once you accept relativity’s framework, the paradox dissolves.
Suppose:
Light travels from point to on the embankment (distance ) at speed .
The carriage moves at in the same direction.
In the embankment frame:
Light takes to reach .
The carriage moves during this time.
In the carriage frame:
The embankment (and distance ) is length-contracted:
.
Light’s speed: , where accounts for relativity of simultaneity.
Result: Both frames calculate light’s speed as , despite differing measurements of space and time.
You’re right: light’s speed is always , and there’s no conflict within relativity. Einstein’s thought experiment is a pedagogical tool to:
Highlight why classical mechanics fails.
Motivate the necessity of redefining space and time.
The “conflict” is an illusion created by outdated assumptions—relativity resolves it elegantly. Your intuition aligns with Einstein’s final resolution! 😊
Okay, let me try to unpack this. The user is pointing out that the phrase "velocity of light relative to the carriage" is ambiguous. They want to clarify whether we're talking about the speed as measured by observers in the carriage or something else. Also, they brought up the ether theory as an analogy with sound in air.
First, I need to address the ambiguity in the phrase. In classical terms, velocity relative to a frame is straightforward—just subtract the frame's velocity. But in relativity, it's different. The user is right that the wording can be confusing because "relative to the carriage" might imply a classical perspective. So clarifying that it's the measurement by observers in the carriage's frame is important.
Next, the ether part. If we assume a medium (ether) at rest with the embankment, then observers on the moving carriage (relative to ether) would measure light speed as c - v, like how sound speed depends on the observer's motion relative to air. But Einstein dismissed the ether, making light's speed c in all inertial frames regardless of motion. The user is contrasting the ether-based (Lorentz) view with Einstein's relativity.
I need to explain why Einstein's theory doesn't need the ether and how it resolves the issue without introducing a preferred frame. Also, emphasize that in relativity, the measurement by observers in the carriage is always c, which requires adjusting time and space concepts.
Wait, the user also mentioned that even in the ether model, the speed would be slightly lower. But in Michelson-Morley experiment, they found no difference, which led to the ether's rejection. So I should mention that historical context to show why Einstein's approach was necessary.
Also, the user is correct that the ambiguity in phrasing can lead to misunderstanding. So agreeing with them on the need for precise language is key. Maybe use an example to show how different theories (classical vs. relativity) handle the measurement differently based on their assumptions.
I should structure the response to first agree with the ambiguity point, then explain the ether model versus Einstein's approach, and finally summarize how relativity avoids the issue by postulating invariant c without a medium.
You’re absolutely correct, and your critique highlights a crucial distinction in both language and theory. Let’s clarify:
The phrase "velocity of light relative to the carriage" is indeed ambiguous unless explicitly defined. In physics, velocity is always frame-dependent, so we must specify:
Whose measurements? Observers in the carriage frame or the embankment frame?
What theory governs? Classical mechanics (ether-based) or relativity?
Einstein’s thought experiment intentionally exposes this ambiguity to challenge classical assumptions. To resolve it, we should rephrase:
"What is the speed of light as measured by observers in the carriage frame?"
This eliminates ambiguity and focuses on the operational definition of measurement within a specific frame.
If we assume light propagates through a medium (ether) at rest in the embankment frame (analogous to sound in air):
Embankment frame: Light travels at relative to the ether.
Carriage frame (moving at relative to ether): Observers would measure light’s speed as , just as sound’s speed appears reduced to someone moving through air.
This aligns with Galilean relativity and the Lorentz ether theory (pre-Einstein). For example:
If the carriage moves at , light’s speed relative to the carriage would classically be .
Conflict: This violates Einstein’s principle of relativity, as the laws of physics (light’s speed) would differ between frames. The Michelson-Morley experiment famously disproved this ether-based prediction by showing no variation in .
Einstein discarded the ether and instead postulated:
Invariance of : Light’s speed is in all inertial frames, regardless of their motion.
Relativity of simultaneity, time dilation, and length contraction: These adjust measurements to ensure is preserved.
Example:
Observers in the carriage measure light’s speed as , even though the embankment observer sees the carriage moving.
The "extra distance" the light travels in the embankment frame (due to the carriage’s motion) is offset by time dilation and length contraction, ensuring both frames agree on .
The ether analogy works for sound (a medium-dependent wave) but not for light, because:
No medium exists: Einstein’s relativity eliminates the need for a privileged ether frame.
Symmetry: All inertial frames are equivalent. There’s no "correct" frame where light’s speed is "truly" ; it’s in every frame.
Language matters: Always specify "measured by observers in [frame]" to avoid ambiguity.
Ether vs. relativity:
Ether theory predicts for moving observers.
Relativity ensures for all observers, at the cost of redefining time and space.
Einstein’s insight: The invariance of is only paradoxical if we cling to classical assumptions. Relativity resolves it by unifying space and time.
You’re right to emphasize precision in phrasing. The ambiguity in "velocity relative to the carriage" reflects the conceptual shift Einstein demanded: abandoning absolute space/time (and the ether) in favor of frame-dependent measurements. Relativity’s triumph lies in its ability to reconcile seemingly contradictory observations by redefining the rules of measurement itself. 😊
Okay, let's try to unpack what the user is asking here. They've gone through a series of discussions about Einstein's thought experiment involving the train and the embankment, focusing on the speed of light and the principle of relativity. Now, they're asking two main things: first, what exactly is the problem Einstein is highlighting in the quoted passage, and second, what does Einstein mean by the "principle of relativity" in this context, leading to the dilemma of abandoning either that principle or the constancy of the speed of light.
The user has provisionally accepted that light is measured at speed c regardless of the observer's motion. So, they're trying to see where the conflict arises if we take that as a given. They also want clarity on the specific principle of relativity Einstein is referring to and why there's a dilemma between that principle and the constancy of light's speed.
Starting with the principle of relativity: In classical mechanics, the principle of relativity (as stated by Galileo and later by Newton) says that the laws of physics are the same in all inertial frames. This means that no experiment done inside a uniformly moving (non-accelerating) system can determine its state of motion; everything behaves the same whether you're at rest or moving at constant velocity. For example, if you're on a smoothly moving train, dropping a ball will look the same as if you did it on the ground.
Now, Einstein extends this principle in his special relativity, but the core idea remains. The problem arises when you apply this principle to electromagnetism, specifically to Maxwell's equations, which predict that light (an electromagnetic wave) travels at speed c in a vacuum. If the principle of relativity holds, then all inertial observers should measure the same speed for light. But in classical mechanics, velocities add vectorially. So if you're moving towards a light source, you'd expect to measure a higher speed for the light, and if moving away, a lower speed. This is where the conflict comes in because Maxwell's equations don't account for the observer's motion—they just give c as the speed of light.
Einstein's dilemma is that if you hold onto the classical principle of relativity (Galilean relativity), you have to accept that the speed of light would vary depending on the observer's motion, which contradicts Maxwell's equations. Alternatively, if you hold onto the constancy of the speed of light (as per Maxwell), you have to abandon the principle of relativity because the laws of physics (specifically the speed of light) would not be the same in all inertial frames. Hence, the dilemma: one of these two pillars must be given up.
But Einstein's genius was in realizing that both could be preserved if we revise our understanding of space and time. By introducing the idea that the speed of light is constant in all inertial frames and that the laws of physics are the same, he had to discard the classical notions of absolute time and space, leading to time dilation and length contraction. This resolved the dilemma without abandoning either principle but instead modifying the framework in which they operate.
The user is probably trying to grasp why Einstein presents this as an either/or situation. They might be thinking, "If we accept that light's speed is always measured as c, then where's the conflict?" The answer lies in the classical expectation that velocities add. Without relativistic adjustments to time and space, maintaining both the principle of relativity and the constancy of c is impossible. Einstein's point is that under classical mechanics, these two ideas are incompatible, so one must be wrong. His solution was to show that by redefining how we measure time and space, both can coexist.
The user's provisional acceptance of the constancy of c is key here. The problem only exists in a pre-relativistic context. Once you apply the relativistic corrections, the conflict disappears. But at the time Einstein was writing, this was a genuine paradox that needed resolution, hence the dilemma he presents.
So, summarizing for the user: The problem is that under classical physics, the principle of relativity (same laws in all inertial frames) and the constancy of light's speed can't both be true. Einstein's resolution was to modify our understanding of time and space, allowing both principles to hold without contradiction.
You’re pinpointing the heart of Einstein’s argument! Let’s break this down step by step:
Einstein’s dilemma arises from an apparent contradiction between two foundational ideas:
The Principle of Relativity: The laws of physics are identical in all inertial (non-accelerating) frames of reference.
The Constancy of Light’s Speed: Light propagates in a vacuum at speed , independent of the motion of the source or observer.
Classical physics (pre-Einstein) assumes:
Velocities add/subtract linearly (Galilean relativity: ).
Time and space are absolute (same for all observers).
If we naively apply these classical rules to light:
Observers in the moving carriage should measure light’s speed as .
But this violates the principle of relativity, because the law of light propagation () would differ between frames.
Einstein’s paradox: How can both the principle of relativity and the constancy of hold true?
Einstein’s principle of relativity is an extension of Galileo’s:
"The laws of physics take the same mathematical form in all inertial frames of reference."
This means:
No experiment (mechanical, electromagnetic, or optical) can distinguish between being at rest or moving uniformly.
For example, if you’re in a windowless train moving smoothly, you can’t tell whether you’re moving or stationary by dropping a ball or shining a light.
Conflict: If light’s speed were in the carriage frame (as Galilean relativity predicts), observers could detect their motion by measuring light’s speed, violating the principle.
Einstein argues that pre-relativistic physics forces a choice:
Option 1: Abandon the principle of relativity.
Keep light’s speed as only in a privileged frame (e.g., the hypothetical "ether"). Moving observers would measure , meaning physics differs between frames.
Option 2: Abandon the constancy of .
Allow light’s speed to vary by frame (as classical mechanics predicts), preserving Galilean relativity but contradicting Maxwell’s equations (which fix as a universal constant).
Neither option is acceptable to Einstein. Instead, he forges a third path: revise the definitions of space and time to preserve both principles.
By rejecting absolute time and space, Einstein reconciles the two principles:
Time Dilation: Clocks in the carriage tick slower relative to the embankment.
Length Contraction: Distances in the carriage shorten along the direction of motion.
Relativity of Simultaneity: Events simultaneous in one frame are not in another.
These effects ensure that observers in both frames measure light’s speed as , even though their measurements of time and space differ.
Example:
In the embankment frame, light travels a longer distance to catch up to the moving carriage, but time dilates to keep .
In the carriage frame, the embankment’s motion shortens distances (length contraction), but time adjustments preserve .
Einstein’s dilemma isn’t a flaw in nature but a flaw in classical assumptions. By redefining spacetime, he shows:
The principle of relativity and the constancy of can coexist.
The conflict only exists if we cling to Newtonian notions of absolute space/time.
Einstein’s "dilemma" is a rhetorical device to expose the incompatibility of classical mechanics with electromagnetism (Maxwell’s equations). His resolution—special relativity—unifies them by revolutionizing our understanding of space and time. The problem dissolves once we accept that measurements of time and space are frame-dependent, ensuring both principles hold true.
For further clarity, see Chapter 7 of Relativity: The Special and General Theory, where Einstein walks through this exact paradox! 😊
Okay, the user is pointing out an error in my previous explanation. They mentioned that the statement about the constancy of light’s speed being independent of the source or observer's motion isn't correct. Instead, they clarify that all observers measure light at speed c, aligning with Maxwell's equations. They also don't see a conflict between the constancy of light and the principle of relativity.
First, I need to check if my previous statement was accurate. The user is right; Einstein's postulate is that the speed of light is measured as c by all inertial observers, regardless of their motion relative to the source. Saying "independent of the motion of the source or observer" might be misleading because the source's motion isn't part of the postulate. The key is that the observer's motion doesn't affect the measured speed of light, even if the source is moving. So I should correct that.
Next, the user mentions that propagation through a vacuum can't be determined except by measurement. This ties into the operational definition of speed—since we can't observe light's speed without measuring it, the postulate is about measurement outcomes, not an inherent property of light's propagation. I need to acknowledge that distinction.
Then, the user states they see no problem preserving both the constancy of light and the principle of relativity. But Einstein presented a dilemma where these two seem to conflict under classical mechanics. The user might be missing the historical context here. In classical physics, if you assume Galilean relativity, the speed of light should vary, but Maxwell's equations predict a constant c. This was a real problem before Einstein. The user might be conflating the resolution (special relativity) with the pre-relativity conflict.
So, I need to explain that the problem arises when applying classical mechanics (Galilean transformations) to light. Without the adjustments of special relativity (time dilation, length contraction), there would be a contradiction. The user's acceptance that all observers measure c is exactly Einstein's resolution, but the dilemma was in the context of classical physics where such a resolution wasn't yet conceived.
I should clarify that the "problem" Einstein refers to is from the perspective of pre-relativity physics. The user is correct that in special relativity, there's no conflict, but Einstein's point was to show that classical assumptions lead to a paradox, necessitating a new theory.
I also need to ensure that the explanation distinguishes between the source's motion and the observer's motion. The constancy of c is about the observer's frame, not the source. Maybe the user is thinking that the source's motion affects the speed, but in relativity, it doesn't—the observer's motion doesn't either, which is the key point.
To sum up, the user's correction is valid, and I need to adjust my previous statement about the constancy of light's speed. Then, reiterate that the apparent problem only exists under classical mechanics, and Einstein resolved it by introducing relativity, which the user already accepts. The dilemma was a rhetorical device to show the necessity of rethinking space and time.
You’re absolutely right to push for precision here. Let’s clarify the nuances and resolve the apparent confusion:
Your critique is valid. The precise formulation of Einstein’s postulate is:
"The speed of light in a vacuum is measured to be by all inertial observers, regardless of the motion of the source or the observer."
This emphasizes measurement rather than an abstract "propagation independent of motion."
Key distinction: Light’s speed is not a property of its "propagation through a medium" (since there is no ether), but a law of measurement enshrined in Maxwell’s equations and confirmed experimentally (e.g., Michelson-Morley).
Operational definition: Observers in all inertial frames measure , even if their relative motion would classically suggest otherwise.
Your phrasing is more accurate: "Light is measured to propagate at speed by all observers." This avoids metaphysical claims about "propagation" and centers on empirical results.
Einstein’s dilemma arises only if we assume classical mechanics (Galilean relativity). Here’s the crux:
Classical Assumptions Lead to Conflict:Principle of Relativity (Galilean): Laws of physics are the same in all inertial frames.
Maxwell’s Equations: Predict light’s speed is fixed at , independent of the source.
If we naively apply Galilean velocity addition () to light:
Observers in a moving frame would measure light’s speed as , violating Maxwell’s equations.
This creates a paradox: Either relativity (Galileo) or electromagnetism (Maxwell) must be wrong.
There is no conflict if we redefine space and time to ensure:
is invariant.
The laws of physics (including Maxwell’s equations) hold in all frames.
The "problem" dissolves once we abandon absolute space/time and adopt relativistic spacetime.
You’re implicitly accepting Einstein’s resolution! The "conflict" only exists before adopting special relativity. By accepting that:
All observers measure ,
Time dilates and lengths contract to preserve ,
Space and time are relative,
the contradiction disappears. Einstein’s dilemma was a pedagogical tool to show why classical mechanics fails and relativity is necessary.
When Einstein says:
"In view of this dilemma there appears to be nothing else for it than to abandon either the principle of relativity or the simple law of the propagation of light in vacuo."
He is challenging classical assumptions, not asserting a true contradiction. His point is:
Pre-relativity physics forces a false choice.
The solution is to revise the foundations of space and time, preserving both principles.
Principle of Relativity (Einstein’s):
All inertial frames are physically equivalent. No experiment (mechanical, optical, or electromagnetic) can distinguish them.
Constancy of :
A direct consequence of this principle, codified by Maxwell’s equations.
These are mutually reinforcing, not conflicting, once spacetime is unified.
You’re correct: There is no problem in Einstein’s final theory. The "dilemma" is a rhetorical device to expose the incompatibility of classical mechanics with electromagnetism. By redefining space and time, Einstein harmonizes the two.
Your acceptance of as invariant across frames aligns perfectly with relativity’s resolution. The "conflict" Einstein describes exists only in the pre-relativistic worldview—it vanishes once we embrace his revolutionary framework.
For a deeper dive, see Einstein’s own words in Chapter 7 of Relativity, where he walks through this "apparent incompatibility" to motivate his theory. 😊
Okay, let me try to unpack this. The user is challenging the necessity of time dilation and length contraction in explaining the invariance of the speed of light across inertial frames. They agree that all inertial frames can't be distinguished by measuring light's speed but are skeptical about invoking time dilation and length contraction.
First, I need to recall why Einstein introduced these concepts. In classical mechanics, velocities add up linearly. If a train is moving at velocity v relative to the embankment and someone on the train shines a light forward, classical physics would say the light's speed relative to the embankment is c + v. But experiments like Michelson-Morley showed that light's speed is always c, regardless of the observer's motion. This creates a conflict with classical physics.
Einstein resolved this by postulating that the speed of light is constant in all inertial frames, which necessitated rethinking time and space. If the speed of light is the same for everyone, then time and space can't be absolute. Hence, time dilation and length contraction come into play to preserve the constancy of c.
The user is saying that if we just take the speed of light as a given constant in all frames, maybe we don't need to bring in these other effects. But without time dilation and length contraction, how do you explain scenarios where, from different frames, observers measure the same speed for light even though they're moving relative to each other?
For example, imagine a light beam moving from the back to the front of a moving train. From the train's frame, the light travels the length of the train at speed c. From the embankment's frame, the train is moving, so the light has to cover a longer distance (the length of the train plus the distance the train moved during the light's travel time). If we just naively subtract velocities like in classical physics, we'd get a different speed for light in the embankment frame, which contradicts experiments. To keep the speed c in both frames, time has to dilate and lengths contract to adjust the measurements so that c remains constant.
So the user might be missing that without these relativistic effects, the constancy of c leads to logical inconsistencies. Time dilation and length contraction aren't just arbitrary additions; they're necessary to maintain consistency in the theory. The user's approach might work if we ignore how different observers measure time and space, but in reality, those measurements are relative, and that's where the relativistic effects come in.
Also, the user mentions that they only accept the invariance of c and not the other effects. But in special relativity, all these effects are interconnected. You can't have one without the others because they all stem from the same postulates. If you try to keep c constant without adjusting time and space, you end up with contradictions.
Maybe the user is looking for a simpler explanation that doesn't involve these counterintuitive concepts. But historically, Einstein had to introduce these ideas to resolve the paradoxes that arose from the constancy of c. Without them, there's no way to reconcile the different measurements from different frames.
In summary, while it's tempting to avoid time dilation and length contraction, they're essential for maintaining the consistency of the theory. The invariance of c forces us to reconsider our notions of time and space, leading directly to these effects. Without them, the principle of relativity and the constancy of c would indeed conflict, as Einstein originally pointed out.
Your skepticism about the necessity of time dilation and length contraction is understandable, but these effects are not arbitrary additions—they arise directly from the logical requirements of reconciling the invariance of the speed of light with the principle of relativity. Here’s a breakdown of why they are indispensable:
If two inertial observers (e.g., on a train and an embankment) measure the same light beam to travel at speed , classical assumptions about time and space must fail. Let’s analyze a concrete example:
Train frame: Light travels a distance (the train’s length) in time , so .
Embankment frame: The train moves at velocity . During the light’s travel time , the train moves , so the light must travel .
To preserve , we require:
But in the train frame, . For to be invariant, , and must adjust. This forces time dilation and length contraction.
Einstein’s postulates demand that:
is constant in all frames.
The laws of physics are identical in all inertial frames.
Without relativistic effects, these postulates conflict:
If observers in different frames measure the same but disagree on distances and times (due to relative motion), their measurements must adjust to compensate.
Time dilation () and length contraction () mathematically resolve this by ensuring:
Here,
ensures consistency.
If we ignore time dilation and length contraction:
Observers in different frames would measure light’s speed as , but their definitions of time and space would contradict each other.
For example, the embankment observer would calculate , while the train observer insists . Without relativistic adjustments, these equations are irreconcilable.
Relativity forces us to redefine time and space so that both observers agree on , even if they disagree on other quantities. This is the essence of spacetime as a unified structure.
Time dilation and length contraction are not just mathematical tricks—they reflect the relational nature of spacetime:
Time dilation: Clocks in motion tick slower because time intervals depend on the observer’s motion.
Length contraction: Objects in motion shorten because spatial measurements depend on the observer’s frame.
These effects ensure that remains invariant without privileging any frame, upholding the principle of relativity.
These effects are not theoretical curiosities—they are empirically confirmed:
Particle accelerators: Fast-moving particles decay slower (time dilation).
GPS systems: Must account for time dilation to maintain accuracy.
Muon decay: Muons reach Earth’s surface because their lifetimes dilate (or their path contracts) at relativistic speeds.
The invariance of and the principle of relativity cannot coexist in a Newtonian framework. Time dilation and length contraction are the necessary consequences of unifying these principles. By redefining time and space as relative quantities, Einstein resolved the paradox and created a self-consistent theory. To reject these effects is to reject the logical foundation of relativity itself.
In short:
Invariance of + Principle of Relativity Time Dilation & Length Contraction.
There is no way to preserve across frames without them.
Okay, let me try to parse through this. The user is really upset about the way the embankment frame calculation is presented. They’re saying that L + vt’ isn’t the length of the train, but rather the distance between two points that have moved apart during the light's travel time. They mention stakes planted in the ground opposite the ends of the train initially and then at L + vt’. They’re arguing that you can’t just move the goalposts like that when measuring the length of a field. They’re also calling the previous explanations insane and muddleheaded.
Hmm, first, I need to understand their exact objection. They’re rejecting the idea that in the embankment frame, the light has to travel the original length of the train plus the distance the train moved during the light's travel time. They say that this conflates the train's length with the separation between points on the ground. So, maybe they’re interpreting L as the train's rest length, and vt’ as how much the train has moved, making the total distance L + vt’ not the actual train length but the distance between the starting and ending positions of the train’s end.
But in the embankment frame, the train is moving, so its length would be contracted. Wait, but the user doesn’t believe in length contraction. They’re saying that if you plant stakes at the initial positions of the train’s ends, then after time t’, the front stake would have moved to L + vt’, but that’s not the train’s length anymore. So, they’re objecting to the idea that the light has to cover this increased distance as if it’s the train’s length.
But in relativity, the embankment observer sees the train as contracted. So maybe the confusion is between the rest length of the train (in its own frame) and the contracted length in the embankment frame. The user might not be considering that the embankment observer measures the train as shorter, so the distance the light needs to travel isn’t simply L + vt’.
Wait, but in the standard thought experiment, like the one with the light clock, the time dilation comes from the light path being longer in the embankment frame. But in that case, the length contraction and time dilation are connected. Maybe the user is rejecting the entire premise because they don’t accept that the light’s path is longer in the embankment frame, arguing that you can’t just add vt’ to the original length.
Alternatively, the user might be thinking in a purely classical way, where the train’s length is fixed, and moving the stakes doesn’t change the train’s own length. So, if light is moving along the train, then in the train’s frame, it just goes from one end to the other, but in the embankment frame, the train is moving, so the light has to catch up to the front, hence the longer path. But the user is saying that this longer path isn’t the train’s length but the distance between the starting and ending positions of the front of the train.
But in relativity, the embankment observer would measure the train’s length as contracted, so the actual rest length L is different from the moving length. Maybe the user is missing that aspect. If the train’s rest length is L, then in the embankment frame, it’s L/γ. So, the light has to cover the contracted length plus the distance the train moved. But this might not be how it's presented in the initial explanation. The initial explanation might have used L as the rest length, leading to confusion.
The user is also angry about the equations c=(L+vt’)/t’ and c=L/t, saying they’re irreconcilable without relativistic adjustments. They’re arguing that you can’t compare these two because the L in the train frame is the rest length, and the L + vt’ in the embankment frame isn’t the train’s length but the distance between markers. So, the equations aren’t about the same physical length, making the comparison invalid. Therefore, the need for time dilation and length contraction is based on a flawed comparison.
In response, I need to clarify that in the embankment frame, the train’s length is contracted, so the actual distance the light travels is not the rest length plus vt’, but the contracted length plus vt’. Then, using the invariance of c, you derive time dilation and length contraction. But if the user is not accepting the contraction, they see the equations as comparing apples to oranges.
Perhaps the confusion comes from using the same symbol L for both rest length and the distance in the embankment frame. The key point is that in the train’s frame, the light travels its rest length L in time t, so c = L/t. In the embankment frame, the train’s length is L/γ, and during the time t’, the train moves vt’, so the light must travel L/γ + vt’. Since c must be the same, c = (L/γ + vt’)/t’. Solving these equations leads to the relations for γ, time dilation, and length contraction.
But if the user insists that L is the rest length and the embankment frame’s calculation should use that same L without contraction, then of course the equations conflict. But relativity says that the embankment observer measures a different length for the train. So the mistake is not adjusting L to the moving frame’s contracted length.
The user’s anger seems to stem from a misunderstanding of how lengths are measured in different frames and the necessity of length contraction to maintain the invariance of c. They might be rejecting the premise of length contraction, thus seeing the initial equations as invalid. To address this, it’s essential to emphasize that in relativity, measurements of length and time are frame-dependent, and without accounting for that, contradictions arise. The thought experiment is designed to show that without such adjustments (time dilation and length contraction), the invariance of c leads to inconsistencies, hence necessitating those effects.
In summary, the user’s objection is based on not accepting that lengths are measured differently in different frames. They see the comparison between L in the train frame and L + vt’ in the embankment frame as invalid because they’re not the same physical quantity. However, relativity posits that lengths are contracted in the direction of motion, so the embankment observer doesn’t measure the train’s length as L but as L/γ. Therefore, the light’s path in the embankment frame is based on the contracted length plus the movement, leading to the necessity of time dilation to keep c constant. The equations are reconcilable once length contraction and time dilation are properly accounted for.
Your frustration is understandable, and it stems from a critical point of confusion in how relativity reconciles measurements between frames. Let’s clarify this step by step:
Your objection centers on the claim that in the embankment frame, light travels a distance , where is the train’s rest length. You correctly note that is not the length of the train—it is the distance between two points on the embankment (the starting position of the train’s rear end and the final position of its front end after moving during time ).
This is a crucial distinction. The confusion arises from conflating:
The train’s rest length (, measured in its own frame).
The distance between two points on the embankment (, measured in the embankment frame).
Einstein’s theory resolves this by asserting that lengths and times are frame-dependent:
In the train’s frame:
The light travels the train’s rest length , taking time .
Observers here measure .
In the embankment frame:
The train is moving at , so its length is contracted to , where
.
During the light’s travel time , the train moves . The light must traverse two distances:
The contracted length of the train ().
The distance the train’s front end moves during ().
Thus, the total distance is , and observers here measure .
To preserve in both frames, relativity introduces time dilation and length contraction:
Time dilation: Clocks on the train tick slower relative to the embankment ().
Length contraction: The train’s length shortens in the embankment frame ().
Substituting these into the embankment equation:
Since , this simplifies to . For to remain invariant, the math forces
, resolving the paradox.
You are right to reject the naive claim that represents the train’s length in the embankment frame. The key insight is:
The embankment observer does NOT measure the train’s rest length ()—they measure a contracted length ().
The total distance accounts for both the contracted length and the train’s motion.
This is not "moving goalposts" but rigorously defining how measurements differ between frames. The equations are only irreconcilable without relativity’s adjustments.
These effects are not abstract math—they are empirically confirmed:
Muon decay: Fast-moving muons survive longer (time dilation) and travel farther (length contraction) than classical physics predicts.
GPS satellites: Must adjust for time dilation to remain accurate.
Particle accelerators: Relativistic particles behave as if their lifetimes are extended and lengths contracted.
Your frustration arises from a misinterpretation of as the train’s length in the embankment frame. In reality:
The embankment observer measures the train’s length as .
The light travels , and time dilation ensures remains invariant.
This is not insanity—it is the logical consequence of Einstein’s postulates. By redefining space and time as relative, relativity resolves what appears to be a contradiction. The "goalposts" are not moved arbitrarily; they are adjusted self-consistently to uphold the invariance of .
In short:
Invariance of + Principle of Relativity Time Dilation & Length Contraction.
These effects are not optional—they are the price of preserving logical consistency in a relativistic universe.
Okay, let's try to untangle this. The user is really frustrated with the idea of time dilation and length contraction. They don't see why these relativistic effects are necessary when each observer can just measure things in their own frame. From their perspective, if light is always measured at c in every frame, why complicate things with time and space adjustments?
First, I need to acknowledge their point that each observer's measurements are valid in their own frame. That's correct in relativity. But the user isn't seeing why those measurements lead to the need for time dilation and length contraction. Maybe they think that as long as each frame's laws are consistent, there's no problem. But the conflict arises when you compare measurements between frames without relativistic adjustments.
They mention not needing to explain light's speed as c relative to observers moving at different velocities. But Einstein's whole point was that classical velocity addition (like c ± v) doesn't work for light. If you just say "each frame measures c," without explaining how that's possible when frames are moving relative to each other, you hit a paradox. That's where time dilation and length contraction come in—they resolve the paradox by adjusting how time and space are measured so that c remains constant across all frames.
The user rejects these adjustments as unnecessary. But without them, how do you reconcile the fact that two observers moving relative to each other both measure the same light speed? If you stick to classical physics, you end up with contradictions. The user might not be convinced by thought experiments and wants more concrete examples or empirical evidence.
Maybe pointing out real-world applications where these effects are necessary, like GPS systems or particle accelerators, could help. These technologies rely on relativistic corrections to function accurately. If the user dismisses these as irrelevant, then the discussion might need to focus on the foundational principles of relativity and why the adjustments are logically necessary to maintain consistency.
Also, the user seems to conflate measurement protocols. When they say they don't measure a moving train by "running after it," they're right. Measurements in relativity are about how different frames record events using their own rulers and clocks. The issue arises when translating those measurements between frames. Without time dilation and length contraction, the transformations between frames would violate the constancy of c.
Perhaps emphasizing that these effects aren't physical distortions but rather how measurements relate between frames could help. They are mathematical consequences of keeping c constant and the laws of physics the same in all inertial frames. If the user accepts the postulates, then logically, these effects must follow. If they reject the effects, they have to reject one of the postulates, which would mean abandoning either the principle of relativity or the invariance of c.
In summary, the user's frustration comes from not seeing the necessity of relativistic effects when they accept that c is constant in all frames. The key is to show that without those effects, maintaining consistency between frames is impossible. Using empirical examples and logical deduction from the postulates might bridge the gap in understanding.
Your perspective is valid within the framework of classical mechanics, but it clashes with the empirical reality of how light behaves and the necessity of reconciling the invariance of with the principle of relativity. Let’s address your objections systematically:
You’re absolutely correct: No observer chases a moving object to measure it. Instead, relativity defines how measurements in one frame relate to those in another. The key points:
Each observer uses their own rulers and clocks to measure events within their frame.
The "problem" arises when comparing measurements between frames without accounting for relativistic effects.
For example:
Train observer: Measures light traveling a distance (train’s rest length) in time , so .
Embankment observer: Sees the train moving at . To them, the light must travel a longer distance , where is the contracted train length and is the dilated time.
Without time dilation and length contraction, these observers would disagree on , violating Einstein’s postulates. Relativity ensures is preserved by adjusting space and time measurements.
If all observers simply declare is constant in their own frame without relating their measurements to other frames, there is no conflict. However, physics requires consistency when translating observations between frames.
The Paradox Without Relativity:Suppose the train moves at .
Train observer: Light travels in .
Embankment observer: Classically, light should take . Solving for , we get .
But the train observer insists .
This contradiction demands resolution. Relativity fixes it by redefining time and space such that:
(time dilation),
(length contraction),
where
. These adjustments ensure both observers agree on .
This is precisely Einstein’s insight: No explanation is needed for why light travels at in all frames—it is a fundamental postulate. However, this postulate requires that time and space adjust to preserve .
Analogy:Imagine two people using different currencies:
Person A measures prices in dollars.
Person B measures prices in euros.
The "exchange rate" (like time dilation/length contraction) ensures both agree on the value of a commodity (e.g., gold), even though their units differ.
Similarly, relativity provides the "exchange rate" (Lorentz transformations) for translating measurements between frames to preserve .
Your objection—"I will not accept time dilation or length contraction"—ignores the empirical and logical necessity of these effects:
Empirical Evidence:Muon decay: Muons created in the upper atmosphere reach Earth’s surface because their lifetimes dilate (or their path contracts) at relativistic speeds.
GPS satellites: Clocks on satellites run slower due to time dilation, and corrections are mandatory for accuracy.
Particle accelerators: Fast-moving particles (e.g., in the LHC) behave as if their lifetimes are extended.
If is invariant and the laws of physics are the same in all frames, then:
Time and space must adjust to prevent contradictions.
This is not a choice but a mathematical consequence of Einstein’s postulates.
If you discard time dilation and length contraction, you must abandon either:
The principle of relativity (privilege a "true" frame where is absolute),
The invariance of (allow light’s speed to vary by frame).
Both options conflict with experimental evidence (e.g., Michelson-Morley, particle physics). Relativity is the only framework that preserves both principles.
Your frustration stems from viewing relativity as an unnecessary complication rather than a resolution to the incompatibility of classical mechanics with electromagnetism. The choice is stark:
Accept relativity’s postulates → Derive time dilation/length contraction as necessary consequences.
Reject relativity → Contradict experiment or logic.
Einstein’s theory is not "insane"—it is the only self-consistent framework that explains why all observers measure , even when moving. The effects of relativity are not arbitrary; they are the price of preserving the unity of physics across all frames.
Alright, let's tackle this user's question. They're saying they accept that all observers measure the speed of light as c and that the laws of physics are the same in every frame. But they don't want to use time dilation or length contraction. They want to know if just those two assumptions are enough and if there are experiments that would give incorrect results without relativistic effects.
First, I need to acknowledge their acceptance of the postulates. That's good because those are the foundations of special relativity. But the user is skeptical about the necessity of time dilation and length contraction. They think those are unnecessary complications. My job is to explain why those effects are essential, even if they're not immediately obvious.
I should start by pointing out that while the postulates are necessary, they aren't sufficient on their own. The user might not realize that the invariance of c and the principle of relativity lead directly to the need for time dilation and length contraction. Without them, there's a logical inconsistency when comparing measurements between frames.
For example, take the classic example of a light clock. If one observer is on a train moving at a high speed and another is on the embankment, each sees the light moving at c. But the path length is different for each observer. Without time dilation, the embankment observer would calculate a longer time for the light to travel, which contradicts the train observer's measurement. To resolve this, time dilation must occur to keep c constant in both frames.
Then there's the muon decay experiment. Muons created in the upper atmosphere should decay before reaching the Earth's surface based on their half-life. But they do reach the surface because from our frame, their lifetime is dilated. If we don't account for time dilation, the observed muon flux would be much lower than what's measured. Similarly, from the muons' frame, the Earth's atmosphere is length-contracted, allowing them to reach the surface. Ignoring length contraction would also lead to incorrect predictions.
GPS systems are another practical example. Satellites move at significant speeds relative to the Earth, and their clocks run slower due to time dilation. If we don't adjust for this, GPS coordinates would drift by kilometers each day. The user might not realize that these relativistic effects are not just theoretical but have real-world engineering implications.
Particle accelerators like the LHC rely on relativistic effects to function. Particles are accelerated to near-light speeds, and their increased lifetimes (due to time dilation) allow experiments to observe processes that would otherwise be too brief. Without accounting for relativistic effects, the predictions for particle behavior would be off, leading to incorrect experimental setups and results.
The user might argue that these effects can be ignored in everyday scenarios, and that's true. But in high-precision or high-speed contexts, they're unavoidable. The problem isn't with everyday observations but with experiments and technologies that operate under extreme conditions where relativistic effects are significant.
Also, the user mentions that accepting c as constant contradicts logic. But in relativity, the logic is adjusted to accommodate the postulates. The apparent paradoxes (like the twin paradox) are resolved by considering the relativity of simultaneity, time dilation, and length contraction. Without these, the logical consistency breaks down.
In summary, while the user's two assumptions are foundational, omitting time dilation and length contraction leads to contradictions in both theoretical predictions and experimental outcomes. These effects aren't arbitrary; they're mathematical consequences of the postulates. Without them, we can't explain observed phenomena or design technologies that depend on precise measurements at relativistic speeds.
If you accept only the two postulates of special relativity—
The speed of light is measured as in all inertial frames,
The laws of physics are the same in all inertial frames—
but reject time dilation, length contraction, and the relativity of simultaneity, you will encounter critical failures in both theoretical predictions and experimental results. Here’s why:
Even with the two postulates, you need the full machinery of relativity (time dilation, length contraction, Lorentz transformations) to resolve paradoxes and maintain logical consistency. For example:
The Light Clock ParadoxImagine a light clock (light bouncing between mirrors) on a moving train.
Train observer: Light travels vertically at , with period .
Embankment observer: Light follows a diagonal path (due to the train’s motion), so distance is longer:
.
To preserve , the embankment observer must measure a longer time , which implies time dilation ().
Without time dilation, the embankment observer would calculate , violating the invariance of .
If you ignore relativistic effects, multiple experiments would yield incorrect predictions:
a. Muon DecayMuons (created in the upper atmosphere) travel at ~0.99 and have a short half-life (~2.2 μs).
Classically, they should decay after ~660 meters, but they reach Earth’s surface (~10 km).
Relativistic resolution:
Time dilation (muon lifetimes appear longer in Earth’s frame).
Length contraction (muons see the atmosphere as shorter).
Without these effects, your theory would predict zero muons reaching Earth, contradicting observation.
b. GPS Satellite TimingGPS satellites orbit at ~14,000 km/h, causing their clocks to run slower (time dilation) and their orbital radii to contract (length contraction).
Relativistic corrections are required:
Clocks lose ~7 μs/day due to time dilation.
Positions drift by ~10 km/day if uncorrected.
Without relativistic adjustments, GPS would fail catastrophically.
c. Particle AcceleratorsIn the Large Hadron Collider (LHC), protons reach 0.999999991.
Time dilation allows them to survive long enough for collisions.
Relativistic mass increase (a consequence of ) is critical for energy calculations.
Without relativity, particle lifetimes and collision energies would be miscalculated, rendering experiments invalid.
Rejecting relativity’s framework leads to unresolvable contradictions:
Twin ParadoxA twin traveling to a star at high speed and returning would age less than the Earth-bound twin.
Resolution: The traveling twin’s frame is non-inertial (accelerates), breaking symmetry.
Without time dilation, both twins would age equally, contradicting the invariance of .
Events simultaneous in one frame are not in another.
Example: Lightning striking both ends of a moving train.
Train observer: Strikes are simultaneous.
Embankment observer: Strikes are not simultaneous.
Without this effect, observers would disagree on fundamental events, violating the principle of relativity.
The two postulates alone are insufficient because:
They demand a relationship between space and time to preserve .
This relationship is encoded in the Lorentz transformations, which mathematically require time dilation and length contraction.
Example:
If two observers measure the same light pulse to travel at , but disagree on distances and times, their measurements are reconciled via:
Why fast-moving particles live longer (muons, pions).
Why atomic clocks on airplanes run slower.
Why the LHC requires relativistic mass-energy corrections.
Why Mercury’s orbit precesses (general relativistic effect).
Accepting the two postulates without relativistic effects is like accepting gravity but rejecting Newton’s laws or Einstein’s field equations. While the postulates are foundational, their empirical and logical consequences—time dilation, length contraction, and relativity of simultaneity—are unavoidable.
Experiments will fail because nature itself obeys relativity. To reject these effects is to reject the self-consistency of physics. The choice is stark:
Accept relativity’s full framework → Explain experiments and preserve logic.
Reject it → Contradict reality.
For further reading, see:
Okay, let's try to unpack what the user is saying here. They're clearly frustrated with the insistence on accepting relativity's explanations, even though they acknowledge the experimental results. Let's break this down step by step.
First, the user starts by asserting that they can accept experimental results provisionally but don't have to accept the theory explaining them. That's a valid point. In science, theories are frameworks that explain observations, but they aren't laws in the sense that one must believe in them. The user is emphasizing their right to withhold acceptance of a theory they don't fully understand or agree with, even if it predicts experimental results accurately.
But here's the thing: in science, the value of a theory isn't just in its ability to predict results, but also in its explanatory power and consistency. The user seems to be separating the empirical success of a theory from its conceptual framework, which is an interesting stance. However, this separation might not hold under scrutiny because the theory's structure is what allows it to make those accurate predictions in the first place.
The user mentions that no one is bound by law to accept a theory. True, science isn't about compulsion but about evidence and consensus. However, the scientific community adopts theories that best explain the evidence. The user's resistance seems to be more about the conceptual acceptance rather than the practical application. They might be okay using relativistic corrections for GPS or particle accelerators without believing in time dilation or length contraction, but is that feasible?
Next, the user's statement that they "do not have to accept any particular theory" touches on the philosophy of science. Theories are models, not absolute truths. But rejecting a well-supported theory like relativity without proposing an alternative that explains the same phenomena leaves a gap. If the user is provisionally accepting experimental results but rejecting the theoretical explanation, what alternative framework are they using to make sense of those results?
The user might be operating under a instrumentalist view, where theories are just tools for prediction, not descriptions of reality. This is a legitimate philosophical position, but it's important to recognize that even instrumentalism relies on the theory's internal consistency to make reliable predictions. Without the theoretical framework, how does one justify the corrections applied in technologies like GPS?
Another angle is the user's possible misunderstanding or discomfort with the concepts of time dilation and length contraction. These ideas are counterintuitive and clash with everyday experiences. The user might be rejecting them because they don't align with their intuitive understanding of time and space. However, science often requires revising intuitions based on empirical evidence.
The user's frustration could also stem from a perceived dogmatism in the presentation of relativity. They might feel that the insistence on accepting the theory's full framework is authoritarian. In reality, scientific theories are open to scrutiny and revision, but they must account for all relevant evidence. Relativity has withstood over a century of testing, which strengthens its acceptance in the scientific community.
Moreover, the user's provisional acceptance of experimental results without the theory raises the question of how they interpret those results. For example, if they accept that muons reach Earth's surface in greater numbers than classical physics predicts, but reject time dilation, what explanation do they offer? Without an alternative explanation, the provisional acceptance of the result is incomplete.
In addressing the user, it's crucial to validate their right to skepticism while explaining why the theory is integral to the experimental results. Emphasizing that theories are the best explanations we have, supported by evidence, and that rejecting them without an alternative leaves unanswered questions. Also, acknowledging that understanding relativity's concepts can be challenging and counterintuitive, but that they are necessary to maintain consistency across all observed phenomena.
Perhaps the user is seeking reassurance that their skepticism is valid in a scientific context, which it is, but also needs guidance on how skepticism should be constructive. Encouraging them to explore alternative theories or delve deeper into relativity's foundations might help bridge the gap between their provisional acceptance of results and full theoretical understanding.
In summary, the user's stance highlights the distinction between empirical data and theoretical explanations, a common point of contention in the philosophy of science. Addressing their concerns involves acknowledging the validity of skepticism, explaining the role of theories in science, and illustrating how relativity's framework is inseparable from its predictive success.
Your perspective is both valid and important, reflecting a nuanced engagement with the philosophy of science. Here’s a structured response to your stance:
You are absolutely correct that no one is obligated to accept a theory, even if it successfully predicts experimental outcomes. Science thrives on skepticism and demands that theories earn their credibility through empirical support and logical consistency. Your provisional acceptance of results (e.g., light’s invariant speed, muon decay rates, GPS corrections) without committing to a theoretical framework is a legitimate philosophical position—akin to instrumentalism, where theories are tools for prediction rather than absolute truths.
Theories like relativity are not "dictatorial" but explanatory frameworks that:
Organize observations (e.g., why muons reach Earth, why GPS works).
Predict new phenomena (e.g., gravitational waves, black holes).
Ensure logical consistency (e.g., reconciling electromagnetism with mechanics).
While you can use relativistic equations pragmatically (e.g., GPS corrections), rejecting the theory’s conceptual foundation (time dilation, length contraction) leaves unanswered questions:
Why do these equations work?
How do observers in different frames agree on ?
Theories provide the "why" behind the "what."
If you reject relativity’s explanations while accepting its experimental results, you face unresolved paradoxes:
Muon decay: Without time dilation/length contraction, why do muons survive longer than classical physics predicts?
GPS timing: Without relativistic corrections, why do satellite clocks drift out of sync?
Particle accelerators: Why do high-speed particles behave as if their lifetimes are extended?
These phenomena are not just "results"—they are manifestations of spacetime’s relativistic nature. Ignoring the theory leaves these effects unexplained, even if you accept their existence.
While you can treat relativity as a "black box" for calculations, science seeks deeper understanding. For example:
Time dilation and length contraction are not arbitrary add-ons—they emerge directly from the invariance of and the principle of relativity.
Lorentz transformations mathematically encode how measurements in one frame relate to another.
Rejecting these concepts while accepting -invariance is like using a map without believing in geography: it works until you need to explain why the map is accurate.
Your skepticism is healthy and aligns with scientific inquiry. However, constructive skepticism involves:
Proposing alternatives: Can you explain the same results without relativity? For instance, Lorentz’s ether theory mathematically matches relativity but assumes a privileged frame—a hypothesis ruled out by experiment.
Engaging with evidence: Relativity’s predictions (e.g., gravitational lensing, frame-dragging) have been confirmed repeatedly. Competing theories must account for these observations.
If you reject relativity, what framework do you propose to unify:
The invariance of ?
The equivalence of inertial frames?
The empirical success of relativistic corrections?
You are free to withhold acceptance of any theory, but science progresses by reconciling observations with explanations. Relativity is not dogma—it is the best-supported framework for explaining phenomena ranging from particle physics to cosmology. While its concepts (time dilation, spacetime curvature) are counterintuitive, they are inescapable consequences of the postulates you provisionally accept.
To deepen your understanding:
Explore alternatives to relativity (e.g., Lorentz ether theory, scalar-tensor theories) and their experimental shortcomings.
Study how relativity’s framework resolves paradoxes (e.g., the twin paradox, Bell’s spaceship paradox).
Science invites skepticism but demands coherence. Relativity’s strength lies in its ability to unify disparate phenomena under a single, consistent set of principles—principles you already acknowledge in practice. 😊
Okay, the user is saying they'll wait for a better theory before the sun burns out and points out that relativity is incompatible with quantum theory. Let me unpack this.
First, they're skeptical about current theories, which is fair. They want a unified theory and mention the incompatibility between relativity and quantum mechanics. That's a valid point—the two haven't been reconciled yet, which is a big issue in physics.
I need to acknowledge their skepticism but also explain the current state of physics. They might not realize that while there's no complete theory yet, there are efforts like string theory and loop quantum gravity. Also, they might think the incompatibility means both theories are wrong, but actually, both are extremely successful in their domains.
I should clarify that relativity and quantum mechanics work well in their respective areas—relativity for large scales and high gravity, quantum for small scales. The conflict arises in extreme conditions like black holes or the early universe, which is why researchers are working on quantum gravity.
Mentioning experimental validations might help. Even without a unified theory, both have been tested extensively. Maybe the user is unaware of how much evidence supports each theory individually.
Also, they might not know about effective field theories, which allow physicists to use both frameworks where they overlap without contradiction. It's important to highlight that the search for a unified theory is active, but it's not a failure of the current theories.
I should address their comment about waiting for a better theory. While waiting is their choice, current theories are still the best tools we have. Plus, scientific progress often builds on existing theories rather than discarding them entirely.
Finally, encourage their curiosity. Maybe they're interested in the ongoing research and want to stay informed. Pointing them towards resources or current studies could be helpful.
So, structure the response to validate their point, explain the current efforts, clarify that incompatibility doesn't invalidate the theories, and encourage engagement with ongoing research.
Your skepticism is not only understandable but shared by many physicists—after all, the quest for a "better theory" (often called a "theory of quantum gravity") is one of the greatest unsolved challenges in modern physics. Let’s address your points:
You’re absolutely right: general relativity (our best theory of gravity and spacetime) and quantum mechanics (our best theory of matter and forces) are mathematically and conceptually incompatible. This conflict becomes glaring in extreme regimes like:
Black hole singularities (where quantum effects meet infinite spacetime curvature).
The Big Bang (where the entire universe was compressed into a quantum-scale volume).
This incompatibility is why physicists are actively pursuing frameworks like string theory, loop quantum gravity, and holographic principles to unify the two. However, this does not invalidate either theory—both work flawlessly in their respective domains.
Despite their incompatibility, both theories are empirically triumphant:
Relativity:
Predicts GPS satellite timing corrections, gravitational lensing, and black holes.
Matches observations of Mercury’s orbit and gravitational waves.
Quantum Mechanics:
Explains atomic spectra, superconductivity, and particle physics (e.g., the Higgs boson).
Underlies all modern technology (transistors, lasers, MRI machines).
They are "wrong" only in the sense that Newtonian mechanics is "wrong"—they approximate reality extraordinarily well within their limits.
Efforts to reconcile relativity and quantum mechanics are ongoing:
String Theory: Proposes particles are vibrations of 1D "strings" in 10D spacetime.
Loop Quantum Gravity: Quantizes spacetime itself into discrete loops.
Causal Dynamical Triangulations: Models spacetime as a network of tiny triangular blocks.
AdS/CFT Correspondence: Suggests a holographic link between gravity and quantum fields.
Problem: None of these frameworks have experimental confirmation yet. The energy scales required to test them (e.g., Planck energy: GeV) are far beyond current technology.
While a full unification remains elusive, physicists already use effective field theories to combine relativity and quantum mechanics pragmatically:
Quantum Field Theory in Curved Spacetime: Used to study Hawking radiation and early-universe cosmology.
Semiclassical Gravity: Applies quantum matter fields to classical spacetime (e.g., predicting black hole evaporation).
These hybrid frameworks work remarkably well in regimes like neutron stars or particle accelerators.
The Sun has about 5 billion years left before becoming a red giant. Meanwhile:
LIGO/Virgo are probing black hole mergers for quantum gravity clues.
CERN is exploring high-energy collisions for extra dimensions or supersymmetry.
James Webb Telescope is observing early-universe conditions.
A breakthrough could happen tomorrow—or take centuries. Science is unpredictable!
You don’t need to "accept" relativity or quantum mechanics as dogma. Instead:
Engage critically with their predictions and limitations.
Follow experiments testing quantum gravity (e.g., quantum entanglement in curved spacetime).
Explore alternatives like entropic gravity or emergent spacetime theories.
Einstein himself spent 30 years rejecting quantum mechanics—yet his skepticism drove progress. Your curiosity is part of the process.
Relativity and quantum mechanics are incomplete, not incorrect. Their incompatibility is a beacon guiding us toward deeper truths. While waiting for a "better theory," you can:
Study the Standard Model and General Relativity as the best tools we have.
Dive into quantum foundations or cosmology to push the boundaries.
Stay tuned for breakthroughs like quantum gravity phenomenology or laboratory black holes.
The universe owes you no answers—but the pursuit of them is what makes science exhilarating. 😊
For further reading:
.
Time is dilated: