Monty, the Devil and Marilyn

25 views
Skip to first unread message

Nichael Cramer

unread,
Nov 1, 1991, 10:45:35 AM11/1/91
to

Due to an ill-timed short in the keyboard to your terminal you have just
died rather suddenly and, to your great amazement, find yourself in Hell.

Before you, you see three doors. Standing in front of the doors are Monty
Hall, the Devil and Marilyn Vos Savant.

The Devil approaches you and says the following:

"Greetings. Because you have led a virtuous life and resisted the evils of
C, and because I am a sporting sort, I'm going to give you a chance to buy
your way out of Hell. I shall give you $10 a day and then on our favorite
holiday, AlephNull Day, if you have enough money, you walk away a free being.

"Now there is, needless to say, one slight complication. We don't trust
you to keep track of your own money, so you have to let either Monty or
Marilyn hold the money for you. Don't worry, whatever else they are, they
are totally honest. They do, however, have somewhat different bookkeeping
schemes.

"Monty is somewhat casual in his approach. He will take all of your money
and toss it into his desk drawer. Then, at the end of each business day,
he will reach into the drawer and take out exactly one dollar --as a
service charge for his trouble.

"Marilyn however is much more fastidious and she prefers to do things up
front. Each day, as soon as Marilyn receives your ten dollars, she will
extract her service charge (nine dollars --naturally you would expect to
pay more for such service) and puts the remaining amount snugly away in the
safe behind her desk.

"Now, again, your money is perfectly safe with either one.

"Which do you choose?"

Carl J Lydick

unread,
Nov 1, 1991, 11:24:53 AM11/1/91
to
Possible spoiler follows

If the safe is more secure than Monty's desk, I'd choose Marilyn. While Monty
and Marilyn might both be honest, we have no guarantee that the devil is. I'd
expect him to steal the money from Monty's desk drawer the day before AlephNull
day. Of course, if AlephNull day is infinitely far in the future, it makes no
difference which of the two you pick.
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
Carl J Lydick | INTERnet: CA...@SOL1.GPS.CALTECH.EDU | NSI/HEPnet: SOL1::CARL

Disclaimer: Hey, I understand VAXes and VMS. That's what I get paid for. My
understanding of astronomy is purely at the amateur level (or below). So
unless what I'm saying is directly related to VAX/VMS, don't hold me or my
organization responsible for it. If it IS related to VAX/VMS, you can try to
hold me responsible for it, but my organization had nothing to do with it.

Dave Seaman

unread,
Nov 1, 1991, 12:52:45 PM11/1/91
to
In article <67...@bbn.BBN.COM> ncr...@labs-n.bbn.com (Nichael Cramer) writes:
>"Monty is somewhat casual in his approach. He will take all of your money
>and toss it into his desk drawer. Then, at the end of each business day,
>he will reach into the drawer and take out exactly one dollar --as a
>service charge for his trouble.
>
>"Marilyn however is much more fastidious and she prefers to do things up
>front. Each day, as soon as Marilyn receives your ten dollars, she will
>extract her service charge (nine dollars --naturally you would expect to
>pay more for such service) and puts the remaining amount snugly away in the
>safe behind her desk.

I choose Marilyn's method. Since she never removes any money from the drawer
after it is put there, I am guaranteed aleph-null dollars on aleph-null day.
With Monty's method it is quite possible to have zero dollars on aleph-null
day, or aleph-null dollars, or any amount in between.

--
Dave Seaman
a...@seaman.cc.purdue.edu

Howard Wachtel

unread,
Nov 2, 1991, 4:54:34 PM11/2/91
to

I'll take a shot at this amusing question:

It seems that the point of the problem is to illustrate a familiar
paradox of the infinite. Since Monty reaches into his drawer and pulls
out a dollar "at the end of each business day" from 1 to Aleph Null, for
any positive integer N one can specify the number of the business day at
the end of which dollar number N will be removed from Monty's drawer, which
is another positive integer. Thus, on "Aleph Null Day", all dollars will
have been removed from Monty's drawer and you are stuck in Hell for another
Aleph Null days.
However, with Marilyn's "bookkeeping scheme", she takes out her $9 up
front, so the $1 she puts into her safe is never removed at a later time,
so your nest egg is full on Aleph Null Day.
Should we call this the Monty Hell Problem? :-)


Howard K. Wachtel
University of Illinois at Chicago
U13...@UICVM.CC.UIC.EDU
Phone (312) 975-7970

Bernie Cosell

unread,
Nov 3, 1991, 7:52:35 AM11/3/91
to
U13...@uicvm.uic.edu (Howard Wachtel) writes:

}In article <67...@bbn.BBN.COM>, ncr...@bbn.com (Nichael Cramer) says:
}>
}>"Monty is somewhat casual in his approach. He will take all of your money
}>and toss it into his desk drawer. Then, at the end of each business day,
}>he will reach into the drawer and take out exactly one dollar --as a
}>service charge for his trouble.

} It seems that the point of the problem is to illustrate a familiar


}paradox of the infinite. Since Monty reaches into his drawer and pulls
}out a dollar "at the end of each business day" from 1 to Aleph Null, for
}any positive integer N one can specify the number of the business day at
}the end of which dollar number N will be removed from Monty's drawer, which
}is another positive integer. Thus, on "Aleph Null Day", all dollars will
}have been removed from Monty's drawer and you are stuck in Hell for another
}Aleph Null days.

Perhaps, but your conclusion isn't immediately obvious. The typical
presentation of the paradox is just as you present it, but Nichael _very_
carefully phrased Monty's procedure so it is not so clear what happens.

The problem is that you have to deal with probabilities and a decreasing
series, and the matterof the limite of the series. Roughly [I tried doing the
real calculation, and it was FAR messier than I was willing to plow through],
Dollar bill "N" has a 1/N chance of being taken on the one day. On the
next day, there are N+9 billsin in the drawer, on the third subsequent day
there are N+18, etc. Now, we can ask "what is the prob that this bill is still
in the drawer on day aleph null? Well, P(surviving one day) = (N-1)/N.
P(surviving second day | survived first day) = (N+8)/(N+9), P(surv 3 | surv 2)
= (N+17) / (N + 18). And in general,
P(surv day K | surv day K-1) = (N + (k-1)*9 -1) / (N + (k-1)*9)

P(surv) = PI[all of the conditional probabilities].

Is that limit always zero? I dunno --- I assume there is some easy
demonstration that it is,but this kindof thing isn't one of my strong
points.. In any event, someone ought to provide the proof and lay the
matter to rest [my intuition is tha tht eprob *is* zero, but it is less
clear to me that if I put in the money faster that it stays zero. For
example, if I put in ten dollars the first day, one hundred the second,
one thousand the third, etc, the prob might well be non-zero]

/Bernie\

Matt Ender

unread,
Nov 3, 1991, 10:00:57 AM11/3/91
to
[Lots o' fun posts about AlephNull Day deleted]

Beg pardon for picking nits, but do you think Omega Day (from the
theory of transfinite numbers) would be more imporant?

Now, not to waste my bandwidth on such a tiny nit, here's the amusing
responses to The Devil, Monty Python [sic], and Marilyn Monroe [sic]
problem. 1) The Devil knows you're a mathematician, and that you
know all about Aleph Null. AlephNull Day has nothing to do with Aleph
Null, but is in fact next Tuesday after lunch. The 'have enough
money' requirement is $9.

2) AlephNull Day is when you think it is. But you will need Aleph One
dollars to get out of Hell...

3) The Devil likes you. You only need enough money on Aleph Null Day
to place a 25 cent call to the diety/ies that will take you out of
hell. Of course, to put a twist on this one, "assume 5% inflation per
annum."

4) The Devil is lying. AlephNull Day is _not_ his/her favorite
holiday. Valentine's day is, and you get to puzzle until AlephNull
Day trying to figure out _why_. (For a hint, read alt.angst)

;)

-- Matt

Matthew T. Russotto

unread,
Nov 3, 1991, 3:25:46 PM11/3/91
to

>4) The Devil is lying. AlephNull Day is _not_ his/her favorite
>holiday. Valentine's day is, and you get to puzzle until AlephNull
>Day trying to figure out _why_. (For a hint, read alt.angst)

It's probably the #1 suicide day.
--
Matthew T. Russotto russ...@eng.umd.edu russ...@wam.umd.edu
Your superior intellect is no match for our puny weapons! -- The Simpsons
Just say NO to police searches and seizures. Make them use force.
(not responsible for bodily harm resulting from following above advice)

David Moews

unread,
Nov 3, 1991, 3:28:42 PM11/3/91
to
In article <kh7s8j...@cosell.bbn.com>,

cos...@cosell.bbn.com (Bernie Cosell) writes:
|}In article <67...@bbn.BBN.COM>, ncr...@bbn.com (Nichael Cramer) says:
|}>
|}>"Monty is somewhat casual in his approach. He will take all of your money
|}>and toss it into his desk drawer. Then, at the end of each business day,
|}>he will reach into the drawer and take out exactly one dollar --as a
|}>service charge for his trouble.
|...
[assuming below that Monty removes a randomly chosen dollar on each day]
|... Roughly [I tried doing the

|real calculation, and it was FAR messier than I was willing to plow through],
|Dollar bill "N" has a 1/N chance of being taken on the one day. On the
|next day, there are N+9 bills in in the drawer, on the third subsequent day

|there are N+18, etc. Now, we can ask "what is the prob that this bill is still
|in the drawer on day aleph null? Well, P(surviving one day) = (N-1)/N.
|P(surviving second day | survived first day) = (N+8)/(N+9), P(surv 3 | surv 2)
|= (N+17) / (N + 18). And in general,
| P(surv day K | surv day K-1) = (N + (k-1)*9 -1) / (N + (k-1)*9)
|
|P(surv) = PI[all of the conditional probabilities].
|
|Is that limit always zero? I dunno --- I assume there is some easy
|demonstration that it is, but this kind of thing isn't one of my strong

|points.. In any event, someone ought to provide the proof and lay the
|matter to rest [my intuition is tha tht eprob *is* zero, but it is less
|clear to me that if I put in the money faster that it stays zero. For
|example, if I put in ten dollars the first day, one hundred the second,
|one thousand the third, etc, the prob might well be non-zero]

Right on both counts. If there are a[j] dollar bills in the drawer on
day j, then the probability of a bill we put in on day k surviving
forever is the product (1 - 1/a[k])(1 - 1/a[k+1])(1 - 1/a[k+2])...,
as you point out. This product is 0 iff the sum of the 1/a[j]'s
for j>=k diverges, i.e., iff the sum of all the 1/a[j]'s diverges.
In our case a[j] grows linearly with j so this sum diverges since
the sum 1+1/2+1/3+... diverges; hence the drawer is empty on
day omega with probability 1. However if we were to put in
10^n (or even just n) bills on day n, the sum of the 1/a[j]'s would
converge and each bill would have a probability exceeding some fixed
positive value of surviving, so we would have an infinite amount
of money on day omega, again with probability 1.
--
David Moews mo...@math.berkeley.edu

Keith Ramsay

unread,
Nov 3, 1991, 5:10:04 PM11/3/91
to
In article <kh7s8j...@cosell.bbn.com> cos...@cosell.bbn.com
(Bernie Cosell) writes:
>P(surv day K | surv day K-1) = (N + (k-1)*9 -1) / (N + (k-1)*9)
>P(surv) = PI[all of the conditional probabilities].
>Is that limit always zero?

Yes, it is. Take the log of the term (N+9(k-1)-1)/(N+9(k-1))
=1-1/(N+9(k-1)). By Taylor's theorem, for log (1+x)=x-x^2/2+..., this
will be between -1/(N+9(k-1)) and -2/(N+9(k-1)) for large enough k.
The sum of -1/(N+9(k-1)) goes to minus infinity because it is
comparable to a harmonic series, sum of -1/k. The infinite product is
said to "diverge to 0" (i.e., converge to 0 (!), but not by one of the
terms being 0), because the sequence of logs of partial products
diverges to minus infinity. Hence if Monty is being quite random, the
probability of any dollar bill surviving to infinity is zero.

Keith Ramsay

The Twice Upon A Time Video Dood

unread,
Nov 5, 1991, 2:21:38 PM11/5/91
to
In article <67...@bbn.BBN.COM> ncr...@labs-n.bbn.com (Nichael Cramer) writes:
>"Monty is somewhat casual in his approach. He will take all of your money
>and toss it into his desk drawer. Then, at the end of each business day,
>he will reach into the drawer and take out exactly one dollar --as a
>service charge for his trouble.
>
>"Marilyn however is much more fastidious and she prefers to do things up
>front. Each day, as soon as Marilyn receives your ten dollars, she will
>extract her service charge (nine dollars --naturally you would expect to
>pay more for such service) and puts the remaining amount snugly away in the
>safe behind her desk.
>
>"Now, again, your money is perfectly safe with either one.
>
>"Which do you choose?"

At first this question seemed intuitively obvious. I figured that
you should pick Monty, cos that way you get nine dollars a day,
you'll be out of hell that much quicker.

Then I figured there had to be a trick, so I ran through a few days,
just to see what happens. After ten days, here's what you get.

Day: Monty: Total: Marilyn: Total:

1 10 10-1=9 10-9=1 1
2 10 19-1=18 10-9=1 2
3 10 28-1=27 10-9=1 3
4 10 37-1=36 10-9=1 4
5 10 46-1=45 10-9=1 5
6 10 55 10-9=1 6 (this is saturday, monty extracts
no surcharge)
7 10 65 10-9=1 7 (ditto)
8 10 75-1=74 10-9=1 8
9 10 84-1=83 10-9=1 9
10 10 93-1=92 10-9=1 10

Even if Monty takes his dollar out o day siz and seven, you end up
with ninety dollars to Marilyn's ten. Is there something I'm missing?
It seems too easy.

-lightnin

/| Lightning: (n) A Force of Nature consisting of an electric discharge.
/ |_DeityCo: The Major and Minor Deities Placement Agency
/_ /=======================================================================
/ / |Up the long ladder, and down the short rope, |Email:
/ /_ |to Hell with King Billy, and God bless the Pope, | lightnin
/_ / |if that doesn't do, we'll tear him in two, | @wpi.wpi.edu
/ / |and send him to Hell with his red, white, and blue.|__________________
/ / | -Traditional Irish Children's Song
/ /===========================================================================
|/ "Dark is not one of my favorite colors." -Ralph, the All Purpose Animal.

Nichael Cramer

unread,
Nov 6, 1991, 5:40:27 AM11/6/91
to

Maybe another way to state the Devil's proposition (which has the
advantages of removing the probabilistic issues and of underscoring the
apparent paradox):

"...Each morning we will add $10 to your pile of money. Then, as the
service charge, either

1] Marilyn will remove $9 from the top of the pile

or

2] Monty will remove $1 from the bottom of the pile..."

N

Matthew T. Russotto

unread,
Nov 6, 1991, 4:08:47 PM11/6/91
to
In article <67...@bbn.BBN.COM> ncr...@labs-n.bbn.com (Nichael Cramer) writes:
>

This is a different proposition, and there is no paradox here. In either case,
Joe Damnedsoul ends up with alephnull dollars on alephnull day (assuming
alephnull day is what we all assume it is)

Bernie Cosell

unread,
Nov 7, 1991, 7:00:00 AM11/7/91
to
russ...@eng.umd.edu (Matthew T. Russotto) writes:

}In article <67...@bbn.BBN.COM> ncr...@labs-n.bbn.com (Nichael Cramer) writes:
}>
}>Maybe another way to state the Devil's proposition (which has the
}>advantages of removing the probabilistic issues and of underscoring the
}>apparent paradox):
}>
}> "...Each morning we will add $10 to your pile of money. Then, as the
}> service charge, either
}>
}> 1] Marilyn will remove $9 from the top of the pile
}>
}> or
}>
}> 2] Monty will remove $1 from the bottom of the pile..."

}This is a different proposition, and there is no paradox here. In either case,
}Joe Damnedsoul ends up with alephnull dollars on alephnull day (assuming
}alephnull day is what we all assume it is)

Close, but no cigar: yes this is different and yes there is no
paradox. But they're not the same: Monty will leave you penniless on
alephnull day.

/Bernie\

Phil Alvin

unread,
Nov 7, 1991, 4:53:59 AM11/7/91
to

Help. I've read all the Possible Spoilers and I still don't get it.
I understand limits and probabilities, but it seems to me with
Monty every day you get $10 and every day he takes one. Granted
this may last forever and Monty keeps taking a bill out, but then
you keep giving him more than what he takes out. What am I missing
here?

frustrated,
S

Matthew T. Russotto

unread,
Nov 7, 1991, 1:20:11 PM11/7/91
to

Upon further reflection, it looks like on day N, with you have
(10 - 9)n dollars,
whereas with Monty, you have
10n - n dollars.

On alephnull day, you have

lim (10-9)n == alephnull dollars with marylin and
n->alephnull

lim 10n - lim n = alephnull - alephnull = (could be anything)
n->alephnull

How do you get that Monty leaves you penniless?

Bernie Cosell

unread,
Nov 7, 1991, 2:29:27 PM11/7/91
to
russ...@eng.umd.edu (Matthew T. Russotto) writes:

}In article <khiam0...@cosell.bbn.com> cos...@cosell.bbn.com (Bernie Cosell) writes:
}>russ...@eng.umd.edu (Matthew T. Russotto) writes:
}>
}>}In article <67...@bbn.BBN.COM> ncr...@labs-n.bbn.com (Nichael Cramer) writes:
}>}>
}>}>Maybe another way to state the Devil's proposition (which has the
}>}>advantages of removing the probabilistic issues and of underscoring the
}>}>apparent paradox):
}>}>
}>}> "...Each morning we will add $10 to your pile of money. Then, as the

}>}> service charge,...


}>}>
}>}> 2] Monty will remove $1 from the bottom of the pile..."
}>

}>... But they're not the same: Monty will leave you penniless on
}>alephnull day.

}Upon further reflection, it looks like on day N,

}... with Monty, you have
}10n - n dollars.

}On alephnull day, you have

}lim 10n - lim n = alephnull - alephnull = (could be anything)
}n->alephnull

}How do you get that Monty leaves you penniless?

Because your abstraction into equations isn't proper for the specific problem
at hand. Nichael phrased it very carefully: you put bills in on top and take
them off of the bottom. Let us number the bills. So on day 1 we put in
bills 1-10, on day 2 bills 2-20. On day N we put in bills 10N-9->10N.

In addition, we are told that Monty takes out the bottom bill. So Monty
takes out bill 1 on day 1; bill 2 on day 2; ... bill N on day N.

So now we can ask the question: what bill could possibly be left in the
drawer on day alephnull? The answer is *no* bill: every bill will have
been removed. Hence the drawer must be empty.

/Bernie\

Matt Crawford

unread,
Nov 7, 1991, 7:41:26 PM11/7/91
to
) Monty will leave you penniless on alephnull day.

That cad! That cur! That montybank!

Rob Hutchings

unread,
Nov 7, 1991, 11:12:47 AM11/7/91
to

I think we've all been assuming the standard related paradox, which goes as
follows:

Suppose all the dollar bills are numbered.
Suppose the ones we put in on day n are numbered (10n-9) thru (10n).
Suppose on day n Monty takes out the bill numbered (n).
Now think which bills can possibly be left in after infinity days.

RobH

Rob Hutchings

unread,
Nov 7, 1991, 10:17:39 AM11/7/91
to

FALLACY! you have only proved that each individual dollar bill is taken with
probability 1, i.e. survives with probability 0. All that follows from this
is that the expected amount of money in the drawer on day omega is
(the total number of bills put into the drawer) times (the probability that
each bill survives), which is indeterminate --- RobH

Dave Seaman

unread,
Nov 8, 1991, 11:04:06 AM11/8/91
to
In article <1991Nov7.1...@vax.oxford.ac.uk> dla...@vax.oxford.ac.uk (Rob Hutchings) writes:

>FALLACY! you have only proved that each individual dollar bill is taken with
>probability 1, i.e. survives with probability 0. All that follows from this
>is that the expected amount of money in the drawer on day omega is
>(the total number of bills put into the drawer) times (the probability that
>each bill survives), which is indeterminate --- RobH

Probability is countably additive. The probability of a countable union of
null events still has a well-defined probability of exactly zero.

--
Dave Seaman
a...@seaman.cc.purdue.edu

Matthew T. Russotto

unread,
Nov 8, 1991, 4:26:59 PM11/8/91
to

Huh? Suppose I have a rational spinner-- that is, a spinner with a pointer
which can point to any rational number between 0 and 1. Certainly the
probability that the spinner will point to any particular rational number
is 0, but the probability that the pointer will point to a rational number
between 0 and 1 is 1.

Dave Seaman

unread,
Nov 8, 1991, 4:58:02 PM11/8/91
to
In article <1991Nov08....@eng.umd.edu> russ...@eng.umd.edu (Matthew T. Russotto) writes:
>In article <25...@mentor.cc.purdue.edu> a...@seaman.cc.purdue.edu (Dave Seaman) writes:
>>Probability is countably additive. The probability of a countable union of
>>null events still has a well-defined probability of exactly zero.
>
>Huh? Suppose I have a rational spinner-- that is, a spinner with a pointer
>which can point to any rational number between 0 and 1. Certainly the
>probability that the spinner will point to any particular rational number
>is 0, but the probability that the pointer will point to a rational number
>between 0 and 1 is 1.

And then you can use a bijection between the integers and the rationals in
[0,1] to establish a uniform probability on the integers, such that all
integers are equally likely to be chosen.

Right.

Probability theory is derived from measure theory, and measure is countably
additive. The measure of the rationals in [0,1] is zero, not one. There is no
way to normalize the measure so that you get one.

--
Dave Seaman
a...@seaman.cc.purdue.edu

David G. Caraballo

unread,
Nov 8, 1991, 2:00:22 PM11/8/91
to
>In article <67...@bbn.BBN.COM>, ncr...@bbn.com (Nichael Cramer) says:
>>
>>The Devil approaches you and says the following:
>>
>>"Greetings. Because you have led a virtuous life and resisted the evils of
>>C, and because I am a sporting sort, I'm going to give you a chance to buy
>>your way out of Hell. I shall give you $10 a day and then on our favorite
>>holiday, AlephNull Day, if you have enough money, you walk away a free being.

The Devil WOULD say something like this! We can count days with positive
integers: 1,2,3,4,5,...

To say that we ever reach Aleph_nul Day is tantamount to saying that Aleph_nul
is a positive integer. (We were counting, adding one for each day, and this
process ended in finite time.) This is already a problem, since, given any
positive integer N, the integer N+1 is strictly greater than N, whereas
Aleph_nul + 1 = Aleph_nul, and so Aleph_nul cannot be an integer. Hence, we
can never reach Aleph_nul day, and we see where the Devil gets his
reputation. :)

If, however, the Devil specified a finite amount of money, then either
Marilyn's scheme or Monty's scheme will work, but Monty's would be nine times
as fast. No doubt, though, the Devil wants Aleph_nul dollars.

With either scheme, the amount of money saved by day d, namely 9d or d,
depending on the bookkeeper, will approach Aleph_nul as d-> Aleph_nul, but it
will never reach Aleph_nul, since d can never reach Aleph_nul. It looks like
it's time to make another deal with the Devil...

Here goes...

Mr. Devil, let's assume that I will have enough money on Aleph_nul day to pay
you Aleph_nul dollars. I can save at most $9 per day, so that on the day
before Aleph_nul day, I'd have at least Aleph_nul - 9 dollars, but this equals
Aleph_nul, so I should be released no later than the day before Aleph_nul day.
The day before that, I had at least Aleph_nul - 9 = Aleph_nul dollars, so I
should be released 2 days before Aleph_nul day. Proceeding in this fashion,
it is clear that you should release me right away.

Devil: Oh dear, I hadn't thought of that... (and promptly vanishes in a puff
of illogic) (ala Doug Adams...)


David

David G. Caraballo

unread,
Nov 8, 1991, 1:47:05 PM11/8/91
to
>"Monty is somewhat casual in his approach. He will take all of your money
>and toss it into his desk drawer. Then, at the end of each business day,
>he will reach into the drawer and take out exactly one dollar --as a
>service charge for his trouble.

I tried, but I couldn't resist responding to this one. With either
bookkeeper, you'll have enough money at Aleph_nul day -- not that it will do
you any good since one can never reach that day! There seems to be no doubt
that Marilyn's scheme of saving $1 of each of your $10 will give you enough
money eventually. Monty's scheme can be seen as a paradox, but, as written,
it is not a true paradox.

Let f(t) be the number of dollars Monty has saved for you by day t. Clearly,
f(t) = 9t, since he puts aside nine dollars each day. Now, one can look at
the problem differently. One can define functions in(t) and out(t),
representing the amount of money put into the drawer and taken out, resp.
Again, it is clear that in(t) = 10t, and out(t) = t. Here's the problem.
(All limits below are for t--> Aleph_nul )

Clearly, lim f(t) exists.
IF lim in(t) and lim out(t) exist, and if lim in(t) - lim out(t) is not an
indeterminate form (such as infinity minus infinity), then
lim f(t) = lim in(t) - lim out(t). However, lim in(t) - lim out(t) IS an
indeterminate form, to wit infinity minus infinity, and so this limit is
meaningless (as opposed to zero).

Fortunately, lim f(t) exists. It equals lim 9t = infinity. The apparent
paradox results from (incorrectly) equating lim f(t) with lim in(t)- lim out(t)
and claiming that the latter limit is zero. When subtracting infinity, one
can make statements like "given any particular dollar, it will eventually be
removed...", since it seems that anything minus infinity should be zero, but
this is not the case.

Here's a different way to view the problem. Start numbering the dollars, and
let T(t) be the set of numbers of our dollars at day t. (f(t) equals the
number of elements in T(t), by construction.)

T(1) = {2,3,4,5,6,7,8,9,10}, since a bill, say #1, was removed on day 1.
T(2) = {3,4,5,6,...,19,20}, since a second bill, say #2, was removed on day 2.
T(3) = {4,5,6,7,...,29,30}, since a third bill, say #3, was removed on day 3.
and so on. Clearly, T will not ever decrease in size, and since it increases
in a continuous way, it can never become an empty set.

NOTE: The numberings on the removed bills were arbitrary.Whichever bill
happens to be removed first, we can call it #1 and label the others 2 - 10.
Whichever is removed second, we can call it #2 and label the remaining bills
3 to 20, and so on.

>"Now, again, your money is perfectly safe with either one.
>
>"Which do you choose?"

Either one will work, but Monty seems to be more honest than Marilyn, so I'd
choose him.

David

Rob Hutchings

unread,
Nov 8, 1991, 5:14:25 AM11/8/91
to

The argument can, however, be restored in the following way.
Let the dollar bills be numbered in the order they are put into the drawer,
and let X at any time be the number of the lowest numbered bill in the drawer.
On day n, the probability of Monty choosing the lowest numbered bill is
1/(9n+1) and therefore the expected value of X increases by at least that
amount (possibly more., but that doesn't matter). Hence the expected value of X
on day omega is at least the sum of the series sum(1/9n+1) which is divergent.
I.e. X increases without limit and Monty leaves you penniless. ---RobH

Joe Keane

unread,
Nov 8, 1991, 6:51:29 PM11/8/91
to

Nothing. These people are confused, even David Moews. The result of having
nothing left at the end is not only counter-intuitive; it's just plain wrong.

The last time this came up, it was numbered balls in an urn. I'd say that we
can take it as an axiom that if you remove a ball, it doesn't matter *which*
one you remove, as far as the number of balls is concerned. So it makes no
sense to say that there are an infinite number left if you always take out the
highest-numbered one, but there are none left if you always take out the
lowest-numbered one.

Or, look at the last ball that you put in. Certainly it's still there, or if
you took it out last, then another one you put in at the same time must still
be there. So there must be at least one ball left, and in fact nine out of
every ten that you put in are still there.

So where have these people gone wrong? Simple. Let's look at that last ball.
What number does it have on it? Well, it obviously must be infinite. But uh
oh, they haven't been considering that case. What they're talking about is
whether there are any balls left at the end *with a finite number on them*.
It's interesting to see whether this is likely or not under various
conditions. But you shouldn't claim that there aren't *any* left.
--
Joe Keane, amateur mathematician
j...@osc.com (uunet!amdcad!osc!jgk)

Keith Ramsay

unread,
Nov 9, 1991, 7:38:38 PM11/9/91
to
cara...@phoenix.Princeton.EDU (David G. Caraballo) writes:
>The Devil WOULD say something like this! We can count days with positive
>integers: 1,2,3,4,5,...
>
>To say that we ever reach Aleph_nul Day is tantamount to saying that
>Aleph_nul is a positive integer.

This is assuming the usual (plausible) assumptions about the nature of
time, which are being (implicitly) dropped for the sake of the puzzle.
There's no *mathematical* reason why there couldn't be an infinite
sequence of days, followed by another day afterward (forever and a
day!), however strange this may seem.

In article <51...@osc.COM> Joe Keane <j...@osc.com> writes:
>Nothing. These people are confused, even David Moews. The result of having
>nothing left at the end is not only counter-intuitive; it's just plain wrong.

I beg to differ. If we assume that any sequence of events requires
only finitely many days, then naturally the whole scenario is
impossible. If we don't assume that, then your reasoning doesn't hold
up.

>The last time this came up, it was numbered balls in an urn. I'd say that we
>can take it as an axiom that if you remove a ball, it doesn't matter *which*
>one you remove, as far as the number of balls is concerned.

If X and Y are sets with the same cardinality, x a member of X, y a
member of Y, then X-{x} and Y-{y} have the same cardinality, yes. This
shows that if two urns have the same number of balls on day n, and
if between day n and day n+1 one adds 10 balls to both, and takes 1
from each, that they will have the same number of balls on day n+1 as
well.

*By induction*, this shows that two such urns which have the same
number of balls added and taken away each day, and which started with
the same number of balls on day 0, will have the same number of balls
after any *finite* number n of days have passed. As you know, this
form of mathematical *induction* applies to finite sequences only. (It
is, in effect, a definition of "finite".)

>So it makes no
>sense to say that there are an infinite number left if you always take out the
>highest-numbered one, but there are none left if you always take out the
>lowest-numbered one.

It certainly does make sense. The assumptions are that balls (bills)
are individuals, that a ball (bill) will be present on day aleph-0 if
it was placed there on a finite day, and never removed on any later
finite day, and that a ball will be absent on day aleph-0 if it was
absent on some finite day, and never added again on a later day.

People also have trouble with Zeno's paradox, until it occurs to them
that there isn't necessarily any problem with there being infinitely
many events in between two events. I for one don't see any inherent
problem with there being an infinite sequence of events, followed by
more action later. Some kind of continuity assumption is required,
however, if we're to be able to tell what's going to happen.

Our solution is implicitly assuming a kind of "physics" for a world
("Hell") in which time doesn't behave the way we expect it to. Given
that it's a puzzle, these seem reasonable assumptions. Formulating a
complete "physics" for our "hell" would be harder- the assumptions
I've mentioned don't tell us what would happen if on alternate days a
ball is added and taken out of an urn, for example. This is perhaps
why we don't expect there to be any times infinitely far into the
future; our ideas of cause and effect run counter to such ideas.

But let's not get too serious after all; it's a puzzle!

>Or, look at the last ball that you put in.

There's no last ball that was put in. In a finite ordered collection,
there's always a last element, but not necessarily in an infinite
ordered collection.

>So where have these people gone wrong? Simple. Let's look at that last ball.

No, there isn't one!

>What number does it have on it? Well, it obviously must be infinite. But uh
>oh, they haven't been considering that case.

Because there is no such case!

Keith Ramsay

David Moews

unread,
Nov 9, 1991, 8:20:18 PM11/9/91
to
In article <51...@osc.COM>, Joe Keane <j...@osc.com> writes:
|In article <61...@ut-emx.uucp> s...@ut-emx.uucp (Phil Alvin) writes:
||Help. I've read all the Possible Spoilers and I still don't get it.
||I understand limits and probabilities, but it seems to me with
||Monty every day you get $10 and every day he takes one. Granted
||this may last forever and Monty keeps taking a bill out, but then
||you keep giving him more than what he takes out. What am I missing
||here?
|
|Nothing. These people are confused, even David Moews. The result of having
|nothing left at the end is not only counter-intuitive; it's just plain wrong.
|
|The last time this came up, it was numbered balls in an urn. I'd say that we
|can take it as an axiom that if you remove a ball, it doesn't matter *which*
|one you remove, as far as the number of balls is concerned....

Hmmmm. Let me state my thoughts on this:

In the problem with Marilyn and Monty, and in this urn problem (in which,
let's say, the urn starts out empty and on day n+1 we put in balls #10n
through #10n+9 and take out ball #n,) we are given the state of the world on
day 0 (W[0]), and a procedure for deriving W[n+1] from W[n] for all finite n.
Then an inquiry is made as to some property of W[omega]. (Omega is the
number that you count just after you've counted all the natural numbers,
in case that isn't clear by now.) Now W[omega] is not strictly defined by
the conditions of the problem. Clearly it must be obtained by some
limiting process. Let N[i] be the number of balls on day i. We might
assume that our limiting process makes N continuous. Then since, for finite i,
N[i] = 9i, N[omega] must be infinite. This is the argument for having
an infinite number of balls on day omega. However, suppose we look at things
with a finer grain, and consider B[i], the set of balls in the urn on day i.
If the limiting process makes B continuous, in the sense that if a ball is
in B[i] for all big finite i it is in B[omega] and if a ball is absent
from B[i] for all big finite i it is absent from B[omega], then B[omega]
is empty and N[omega] = 0.

Evidently we have to give up continuity for either N or B. I think that
one should make the finer-grained function, namely B, continuous. (So
it does matter which ball you remove.) This is because we can easily
compute N from B but not vice versa: if B[omega] is empty, then
N[omega] is definitely 0, but if we assume N continuous and
hence make B[omega] an infinite set, it is difficult to construct B[omega] in
a non-arbitrary way. I think there might be a construction of an element
of B[omega] here:

|...Or, look at the last ball that you put in. Certainly it's still there, or


|if you took it out last, then another one you put in at the same time must
|still be there. So there must be at least one ball left, and in fact nine out
|of every ten that you put in are still there.
|
|So where have these people gone wrong? Simple. Let's look at that last ball.

|What number does it have on it? Well, it obviously must be infinite....

but it seems rather complicated. Is the idea that we take out ball #3 but
put in #30, take out #30 but put in #300, and so on? If so we would seem to
get a continuum of balls on day omega (one for balls #3, #31, #314, #3141, ...,
one for balls #2, #27, #271, #2718, ..., and many more,) but that's surely too
many. Anyway, why make trouble for yourself? Just set B[omega] to be empty.
--
David Moews mo...@math.berkeley.edu

Howard Wachtel

unread,
Nov 10, 1991, 9:41:33 PM11/10/91
to
In article <1991Nov8.1...@Princeton.EDU>, cara...@phoenix.Princeton.EDU

(David G. Caraballo) says:
>
>>In article <67...@bbn.BBN.COM>, ncr...@bbn.com (Nichael Cramer) says:
>>>
>>>The Devil approaches you and says the following:
>>>
(...and so forth)

>
>The Devil WOULD say something like this! We can count days with positive
>integers: 1,2,3,4,5,...
>
>To say that we ever reach Aleph_nul Day is tantamount to saying that Aleph_nul
>is a positive integer. (We were counting, adding one for each day, and this
>process ended in finite time.) This is already a problem, since, given any
>positive integer N, the integer N+1 is strictly greater than N, whereas
>Aleph_nul + 1 = Aleph_nul, and so Aleph_nul cannot be an integer. Hence, we
>can never reach Aleph_nul day, and we see where the Devil gets his
>reputation. :)
>...

Let's fix this by reformulating the problem
in the following way: Suppose we fix Aleph_Null Day at a
point in the future, and suppose that the Devil gives you $10 at 1/n
of a day prior to Aleph_Null Day, for all positive integers n (and
then Monty or Marilyn disposes of the money simultaneously
in the same fashion as stated in the problem originally). Then
we don't have to worry about never reaching Aleph_Null Day.

>It looks like
>it's time to make another deal with the Devil...
>
>Here goes...
>
>Mr. Devil, let's assume that I will have enough money on Aleph_nul day to pay
>you Aleph_nul dollars. I can save at most $9 per day, so that on the day
>before Aleph_nul day, I'd have at least Aleph_nul - 9 dollars,

Wait a minute--there's no such thing as "the day before Aleph_Nul Day"!

>but this equals
>Aleph_nul, so I should be released no later than the day before Aleph_nul day.
>The day before that, I had at least Aleph_nul - 9 = Aleph_nul dollars, so I
>should be released 2 days before Aleph_nul day. Proceeding in this fashion,
>it is clear that you should release me right away.

I don't think that the inducation works in reverse like that--it would
only prove that for all positive integers n, the Devil could let you
out on day Aleph_Nul - n (if there were such a day!), but not "right
"away", as surely day 0 is not day Aleph_Nul - n for any finite n.

Matthew T. Russotto

unread,
Nov 11, 1991, 2:33:29 PM11/11/91
to
In article <1991Nov8.1...@Princeton.EDU> cara...@phoenix.Princeton.EDU (David G. Caraballo) writes:
>>In article <67...@bbn.BBN.COM>, ncr...@bbn.com (Nichael Cramer) says:
>>>
>>>The Devil approaches you and says the following:
>>>
>>>"Greetings. Because you have led a virtuous life and resisted the evils of
>>>C, and because I am a sporting sort, I'm going to give you a chance to buy
>>>your way out of Hell. I shall give you $10 a day and then on our favorite
>>>holiday, AlephNull Day, if you have enough money, you walk away a free being.
>
>as fast. No doubt, though, the Devil wants Aleph_nul dollars.
>
>Mr. Devil, let's assume that I will have enough money on Aleph_nul day to pay
>you Aleph_nul dollars. I can save at most $9 per day, so that on the day
>before Aleph_nul day, I'd have at least Aleph_nul - 9 dollars, but this equals
>Aleph_nul, so I should be released no later than the day before Aleph_nul day.
>The day before that, I had at least Aleph_nul - 9 = Aleph_nul dollars, so I
>should be released 2 days before Aleph_nul day. Proceeding in this fashion,
>it is clear that you should release me right away.
>
>Devil: Oh dear, I hadn't thought of that... (and promptly vanishes in a puff
> of illogic) (ala Doug Adams...)

Naa, the Devil merely says "Aleph_null dollars? Who said anything about
Aleph_null dollars? I want Aleph_1 dollars."

Ian Collier

unread,
Nov 12, 1991, 10:02:55 AM11/12/91
to
In article <1991Nov07.1...@eng.umd.edu>, russ...@eng.umd.edu (Matthew T. Russotto) wrote:
[I'm sure everyone knows the question by now, so I've deleted it]

>Upon further reflection, it looks like on day N, with you have
>(10 - 9)n dollars,
>whereas with Monty, you have
>10n - n dollars.

>On alephnull day, you have

>lim (10-9)n == alephnull dollars with marylin and
>n->alephnull

>lim 10n - lim n = alephnull - alephnull = (could be anything)
>n->alephnull

OK, I think I have now worked out the answer...

Firstly, the second limit above is not correct. If on day n you have 10n-n
dollars, then on day oo [that's short for AlephNull, by the way] you have

lim (10n-n) and NOT: lim 10n - lim n
n->oo n->oo n->oo

Distributing the limit through the subtraction is not mathematically correct
except under certain circumstances, which are not met here. Hence on day oo
you must have oo dollars.

And secondly, we can express the problem in terms of an infinite summation,
rather than a limit, and roughly the same thing happens. In general, we seem
to have no problem in deciding that the final sum of money you get from
Marilyn is

oo oo
\sum (10-9) = \sum 1 = oo
n=1 n=1

Now the problem with Monty is that people don't seem to want to write

oo
10 - 1 + 10 - 1 + 10 - 1 + ... = \sum 9 = oo
n=1

because Monty takes the dollar from the drawer instead of from the money
which is deposited. (I don't think this makes a difference). However note that
the infinite summation is not "absolutely convergent". It is an unfortunate
fact of mathematics that a summation which is not absolutely convergent may
be rearranged in order to give a whole lot of different answers, including
(in this case) +oo, -oo, 0, and so on. For example, since there are
infinitely many of the numbers 10 and -1,

10 - 1 + 10 - 1 + ... = 10-1-1-1-1-1-1-1-1-1-1 + 10-1-1-1-1-1-1-1-1-1-1 ...

equals zero. Or,

10 - 1 + 10 - 1 + ... = 10+10+10+10+... + -1-1-1-1-1-... = oo - oo

equals undefined.

But the fact is, that since we have a clearly defined order in which to add
up the summation (that is, add 10, take 1, repeat), the correct answer for
the problem is +oo.

Ian Collier
Ian.C...@prg.ox.ac.uk | i...@ecs.ox.ac.uk

Dave Seaman

unread,
Nov 12, 1991, 1:47:20 PM11/12/91
to
In article <1328...@uk.ac.ox.prg> i...@prg.ox.ac.uk (Ian Collier) writes:
>Now the problem with Monty is that people don't seem to want to write
>
> oo
>10 - 1 + 10 - 1 + 10 - 1 + ... = \sum 9 = oo
> n=1
>
>because Monty takes the dollar from the drawer instead of from the money
>which is deposited. (I don't think this makes a difference). However note that
>the infinite summation is not "absolutely convergent". It is an unfortunate
>fact of mathematics that a summation which is not absolutely convergent may
>be rearranged in order to give a whole lot of different answers, including
>(in this case) +oo, -oo, 0, and so on. For example, since there are
>infinitely many of the numbers 10 and -1,
>
>10 - 1 + 10 - 1 + ... = 10-1-1-1-1-1-1-1-1-1-1 + 10-1-1-1-1-1-1-1-1-1-1 ...
>
>equals zero. Or,
>
>10 - 1 + 10 - 1 + ... = 10+10+10+10+... + -1-1-1-1-1-... = oo - oo
>
>equals undefined.
>
>But the fact is, that since we have a clearly defined order in which to add
>up the summation (that is, add 10, take 1, repeat), the correct answer for
>the problem is +oo.

Conditional convergence and rearrangement of terms have nothing to
do with it. The reason Monty's method leaves an indeterminate
amount of money in the drawer is that it is not specified exactly
which bills he removes. Here are three possible scenarios, each
consistent with the original problem statement, giving three
different answers.

(1) On day 1, bills 1-10 go into the drawer and Monty
takes bill 1. On day 2, bills 11-20 go into the drawer
and Monty takes bill 2. On day n, bills (10n-9)
through (10n) go into the drawer and Monty takes bill
n. On aleph-null day the drawer is empty. Proof:
Suppose not. Then there must be a least number n such
that bill n is still in the drawer. But this bill
was removed on day n and never returned to the drawer,
which is a contradiction. The limit analysis fails
because it does not make use of all the available
information, and also because it depends on an incorrect
assumption, namely, that f(aleph-null) necessarily
equals lim f(n). It does not, as this example shows.
n -> oo

(2) On day 1, bills 1-10 go into the drawer and Monty
takes bill 2. On day 2, bills 11-20 go into the drawer
and Monty takes bill 3. On day n, bills (10n-9)
through (10n) go into the drawer and Monty takes bill
(n+1). On aleph-null day the drawer contains one
dollar (namely, bill number 1). All the other bills
have been removed, as explained in (1). Once again,
the limit analysis fails because it does not make use
of all the available information and because it makes
an incorrect assumption.

(3) On day 1, bills 1-10 go into the drawer and Monty
takes bill 2. On day 2, bills 11-20 go into the drawer
and Monty takes bill 4. On day n, bills (10n-9)
through (10n) go into the drawer and Monty takes bill
(2n). On aleph-null day the drawer contains aleph-null
dollars (all the odd-numbered bills). All the
even-numbered bills have been removed. Once again,
the limit analysis fails because it does not make use
of all the available information. The assumption
about limits happens to work out in this case (but
only because I chose my assumptions in such a way as
to make it happen).

--
Dave Seaman
a...@seaman.cc.purdue.edu

D. J. McCarthy ~

unread,
Nov 12, 1991, 10:14:19 PM11/12/91
to
a...@seaman.cc.purdue.edu (Dave Seaman) writes:

> Conditional convergence and rearrangement of terms have nothing to
> do with it. The reason Monty's method leaves an indeterminate
> amount of money in the drawer is that it is not specified exactly
> which bills he removes.

There's still something... I don't know... unbelievable about
determining how much money is left in the drawer solely on which dollar
is taken out every day. Yes, there are proofs, and I can follow them
and agree with the outcome, but it still leaves a bad taste in my mouth
- and I don't trust them as much as I feel they need to be.

How about a scenario that you don't mention - namely, that
Monty takes a dollar at random? On the first day the probability of
each dollar remaining is 9/10. On the second day, each of the first
ten dollars have a staying probability of, what, (9/10) * (18/19)
[this is undoubtedly incorrect] and each of the second ten dollars has
a probability of staying of 18/19. The rest of the days are too
strenuous for my flu-modified brain to figure out at the moment.

Anyone want to take this train of thought to a depot?

--
| D. J. McCarthy Qui nos rodunt confundantur
| dmc...@swtec1.intel.com et cum iustis non scribantur.
| ...!intelhf!mipos3!modl01!dmccart Io!

David R. Morrison

unread,
Nov 13, 1991, 4:16:44 AM11/13/91
to

> The reason Monty's method leaves an indeterminate
> amount of money in the drawer is that it is not specified exactly
> which bills he removes. Here are three possible scenarios, each
> consistent with the original problem statement, giving three
> different answers.

> [proof that removing that the bottom bill => f(aleph-null) = 0]

> [proof that removing that the next to bottom bill => f(aleph-null) = 1]

> [proof that removing that the bottom even bill => f(aleph-null) = oo]

Just a few points to ponder:

Suppose there was a gremlin that came in every night and reordered the
bills. As far as Monty and you proof know, nothing has changed. But
now I can transfer from one of your proofs to the other.

If this gremlin doesn't change the problem, does it matter which bill
Monty removes?

If this gremlin does change the problem, how does it? The total number
of bills is unaffected (don't tell me it messes up your accounting...the
way you do you accounting has no affect on how many are actually there).

Does removing an infinite amount of something mean there's nothing left?

Would this Monty Hell argument work with the IRS, if you got taxed on
aleph-null day?

Joe Keane

unread,
Nov 12, 1991, 12:22:32 AM11/12/91