Hi Carrie,
Very interesting paper. You say without much explanation on pages 4-5 that activities can't be individuated functionally, and that functionalism was (at least implicitly) committed to viewing functional realizers as objects rather than activities. Both these claims seem false to me, so I wanted to ask you about them.
Let's take the activity of straightening the shaft of an arrow. I'd be inclined to say that the activity of my whittling off this piece of this arrow could realize that general activity. Of course that general activity could also be realized in other ways, e.g., by my sanding off part of an arrow, or by my steaming a crooked arrow and clamping the now-pliable wood into a straight position. Isn't this an example of (multiple) realization of activities by activities?
Similarly, I thought that one of the classic examples of multiple realization was that pain could be realized by c-fibers *firing* or by pneumatic chambers *expanding*, etc... So it seems to me that, from the beginning, functionalists were open to the idea that functional realizers might be a form of activity, again contrary to what you say on page 4.
I also think there can also be kinds of activities that are functionally individuated. E.g., my whittling a stick counts as an activity of arrow-straightening precisely because of the role that this activity plays alongside other activities (e.g., crafting an arrowhead and affixing it to the stick) in over-all arrow production. [Probably it would be better to instead construe these teleofunctionally, as it's very often better to move from functionalism to teleofunctionalism, but that's getting us into issues orthogonal to your question of whether activities can be typed functionally/teleofunctionally.]
So, anyway, I wanted to invite you to say more about why you thought activities couldn't realize functional roles, and why there couldn't be functional kinds of activities.
Thanks!
-Justin
Hi Carrie!
I confess that I had the same worry here as Justin.
Maybe the following could provide a different response to him?
You could draw a distinction between two claims about X: (i) X is individuated in terms of causes and effects and (ii) X is multiply realisable.
Functionalism asserts (i) is true of mental states as a way of securing (ii).
The claim in the paper only concerns (i): activities are not individuated in terms of their typical causes and effects. You don’t mention multiple realisation at all.
Perhaps a way of keeping Justin and others on board would be to not rule out that activities can be multiply realised (as Justin’s examples suggest). Instead, just say that activities are not individuated in terms of their typical causes and effects. On such a view, activities would be multiply realisable for different reasons: e.g. because they involve abstract dynamical properties that can occur in a number of different ways.
This seems to be true of your example of diffusion. A common way of understanding this is that a material in a medium diffuses iff it satisfies the diffusion differential equation. The diffusion equation is an abstract dynamical description, which many different physical substrates can satisfy in different ways.
Maybe such cases are not truly speaking cases of realisation. But I suspect that insisting on this may prove a distraction for you. After all, realisation is a term of art—perhaps it does serve a purpose to include these kinds of cases in its heading.
Might this provide an easier line to defend?
[Repost: originally posted in the wrong place]
Hi Carrie!
Great paper! I found it very stimulating and helpful!
Just a quick question on how to get a grip on the overall positive view. I kept wondering: what are the entities?
Let’s suppose we switch to the activity-based view. However, it seems that, even on this view, the mind can’t be all activities—there have to be some objects on which the activities operate—activities involve something doing an activity. A cell isn’t entirely activities—it is composed of entities (ions, proteins, etc.) and activities (diffusion, binding, etc.).
On the act-object view, we have a story that involves both entities and activities: the entities are information-bearers (the mental representations), and the activities are the attitudes and inferences in which the information-bearers participate. On the adverbial view, I wasn’t sure what the relevant entities are.
I guess that one answer that an adverbialist could give is to say that the act-object view is, in one sense, right—there are information bearers, and activities that those information-bearers enter into. However, the act-object view is wrong in a second sense: if one looks more closely at those information-bearers, one can see that they are also activities themselves.
Then the question arises of what are the entities undergoing activities in the case of the information-bearers. Is the right thing to say here that the entities are neurological or physical entities, and they are undergoing some information-bearing or semantic activity?
But then it doesn’t seem so different from the old act-object view. That view also said that information-bearers are neurological entities undergoing distinctively semantic activity. So I was a bit puzzled on what the contrast was between the two views—whether the act-object view really is committed to mental representations being entities in a different sense from the adverbialist.