On the big picture:
I agree that, in general, it is difficult to see how philosophy can make substantive claims about the nature of reality without some empirical input. But in the case of consciousness, it seems to me we have a non-observational source of data that must be respected by any metaphysical theory: the certain knowledge each of us has of the existence of phenomenal consciousness. Science can tell me my pre-theoretical concepts get things badly wrong: maybe our folk concepts of ‘time’ and ‘freedom’ are not strictly satisfied. But when I’m in agony, and I form a phenomenal concept ‘feeling like that’, I know for certain that that very concept is satisfied, and hence any metaphysical theory that cannot account for the satisfaction of this concept is certainly false.
We can then have a debate about whether the physicalist can account for the satisfaction of this concept. The type-A physicalist tries to do so by giving a causal analysis of phenomenal concepts; the type-B physicalist tries to do so by giving a semantic externalist account of phenomenal concepts. I reject physicalism as I think these accounts of phenomenal concepts are incredibly implausible. But even if you don’t agree with me on this, you must surely concede that there is a source of data which is insulated from empirical refutation: my concept ‘feeling like that’ is certainly satisfied (in contrast to my pre-theoretical concepts of ‘time’ and ‘freedom’).
On the specific details:
Do you mean to suggest that Chalmers may have an impoverished notion of the physical in taking the physical world to be pure structure/dynamics? If so, I’m not sure how this criticism is supposed to work, give that – as you acknowledge – he is open to Russellian monism.
Hi Eric,
Interesting paper. I definitely share your horror at the immodesty of much a priori philosophy. Here's a couple of quick questions.
(1) I was surprised that you didn't focus more on the question of how confident we could be that there isn't an appearance/reality distinction for conscious-experience. Such supreme confidence has always struck me as the height of philosophical immodesty! Worse, it seems to me that there are also plenty of uncontroversial examples: aspects of my conscious experience that, after having my attention drawn to them, I'm confident were there all along, even though they weren't apparent to me before. E.g., someone might point out that my experience of a light that had recently appeared steady to me was actually a gently pulsating experience, or that my experience of snow-shadows that had appeared pure grey to me before, actually was a bluish experience all along (this example is from John Pollock). Simple examples like these show that not all aspects of a conscious experience are immediately apparent, which invites the question of how many other not-so-apparent aspects of conscious experience might be lurking there, including perhaps even some underlying physical/functional essence...
(2) In note 11 (page 14) you suggest that in cases of apparent causal overdetermination by the mental, there might actually be distinct *effects*, so that these might not actually be causal overdetermination afterall. And you say this can be supported by the same sorts of multiple-realizability arguments that show that mental causes can be multiply realizable. I'd like to hear more about how this would work.
E.g., take the effect of there being a japanese maple tree at that particular spot. I grant that there's a purely physical explanation of this, and I'd also like to say that there is a psychological explanation for this (involving my desire to have such a tree there). I also grant that there are multiple ways that the psychological states in question could have been realized. But I don't see any corresponding ways that the tree's being there could have been realized. I do see that it could have been there and a slightly different shape, color, etc, but none of those seem to correspond to the ways in which my mental state was multiply realizable.
Perhaps you mean that there are a multitude of different fine-grained states that would have equally satisfied my desire, and that the psychological explanation really can explain only the general effect of having one-or-other of these configurations obtain, whereas the purely physical explanation can explain only some much more specific effect? What would you say about a case in which I have a maximally specific desire (or rather precisely as specific as physical explanation is, which might still allow Heisenberg uncertainty, etc...)? Would this be a case of overdetermination, or do you still think there are different effects to be explained?
Anyway, I'm curious to hear more about this (and am sorry for pouncing upon a tangential footnote).
Thanks!
-Justin
Thank you for reading the paper and for all the comments -- much appreciated! Sorry I’m a bit slow in responding.
Graeme: Yes, my understanding of the a priori here is rather naïve. I certainly think that the a priori has something to contribute to “empirical” questions. I don’t have a position on the C.I. Lewis proposal, though. (It reminds me of Grice/Strawson versus Quine on the dogma.)
Philip: I am willing to grant that when it comes to certain phenomenal mental states non-observational data must be respected, as you state. But I wouldn’t go so far as to claim that these data provide us with the essences of those mental states. The data could be respected as telling us that we are in those phenomenal states without informing us (decisively, at least) of their essences.
My point against Chalmers isn’t just the straightforward point that he might have an impoverished understanding of the physical as structural/dynamical. I think I had two main points against the zombie argument. First, we can have confidence in a metaphysical necessity on empirical grounds even if we don’t yet know how/why it obtains. Realization, I think, is best understood as a kind of metaphysical necessitation. And we can know (or be justified in believing) that a realization relation holds without seeing how/why it holds – like knowing that water is chemically realized even before discovering how this is so. Second, if we have some reason to think that phenomenal consciousness is physically realized, then the assumed lack of an appearance/reality distinction can then explain why either a) sameness of physical facts but without phenomenal consciousness is not ideally imaginable or b) it is ideally imaginable but not metaphysically possible. a) is even more palatable given that ideal conceivability is a pipe dream. And b) would not be an unacceptable exception to the conceivability-possibility claim, contrary to what Chalmers claims. Rather, the empirical grounds for believing it is a case of metaphysical necessitation (realization) combined with, critically, the lack of an appearance-reality distinction explains why this is a unique exception.
Justin: Yes, I am also skeptical of the claim that there is no appearance/reality distinction for phenomenal consciousness. Given the theme of my paper (immodesty), I should probably add this point. Thanks for bringing it up. I just wanted to grant as much as possible to the argument. But I also wanted to show that that very premise can also be used to help undermine the zombie argument (see my response to Philip above).
About the multiple realizability of effects. Take your example, where the effect is supposed to be a Japanese maple being at that particular spot. The cause involves, say, a desire that is multiply realizable – a desire that the tree be right there. What’s the psychological effect here? Well, the desire causes a series of actions – going to the nursery, digging a hole, planting the tree, etc. These actions are multiply realizable just as much as is the desire itself. I’m not inclined to say that microphysical “causes” caused these actions, because the actions were not sensitive to those precise details. (Here we might disagree, especially if you are more Davidsonian about the causal relata.) But, those actions are sensitive to his beliefs and desires – e.g., if he no longer wanted the tree there, it wouldn’t be planted there.
Now, you might want to grant me all this and still say that the tree’s being there is not multiply realized, even if the actions are. Well, his desires aren’t maximally determinate here. His desires caused the tree to be, say, in that general vicinity (but not in that maximally determinate spot). The microphysical facts caused the tree to be in that maximally determinate spot. I think that’s what I want to say. And if the desire were maximally determinate (very unlikely), I might accept this as overdetermination. But, I’d still point out that the intermediate actions in the causal chain that produced that effect (going to the nursery, etc.) were probably multiply realizable. Regardless, as you point out, this doesn’t bother me too much. Since I am not bothered by this kind of overdetermination, I wouldn’t have a problem if the true metaphysics of causation had (contrary to what I think) that consequence.
Ted: I’m not just suggested an epistemic gap. The claim is that we have a concept that we know for certain is satisfied (phenomenal consciousness). This has ontological implications, namely that whatever demands the concept of consciousness makes on reality, those demands are satisfied. My overall view – although I have not argued for that here – is that there is no plausible account of the concept of consciousness such that its satisfaction is consistent with physcialism; therefore physicalism is false.
But if Russellian monism is true, then the mental is realised/metaphysically necessitated by the physical (in terms of its intrinsic nature rather than its structural/dynamic features). So I’m not clear why, or even how, you are disagreeing with Chalmers. Do you have an argument to the conclusion that we ought to think that consciousness is realised by the structural/dynamic features of the physical?
Hi Eric! I really liked the paper! I’m really sympathetic with your big picture. I’m was just thinking about being devil’s advocate here trying to come up with a few random worries. Please ignore this if it is not useful!
My main worry was about the evidence that physicalism is the default reasonable position: i.e. we should accept that P metaphysically necessitates Q pending good reasons otherwise (reasons that Chalmers fails to provide on your view).
You give three reasons why we should have some prior commitment to the belief that P metaphysically necessitates Q.
I was wondering if you could explain them a bit more?
But maybe I misunderstood your position, and you are not shooting to provide reasons that would convince a non-physicalist?
Erik
ON THE BIG PICTURE (I forgot to post this part of my last comment (which was in response to your claim about the starting data being that we are in conscious states, but not what their essences are):
My
starting point is not that we have data about the essence of mental states. My
starting point is that we have concepts that we know for certain are satisfied.
We can then have an argument about what those concepts are like, for example,
whether or not they reveal the essence of the states they denote. But if you
agree with me that we have concepts that we know for certain are satisfied,
then we are in a very special epistemic situation relative to other
metaphysical debates. Do you agree with this?
ON THE DETAILS
Denying (i) the ideal conceivability of zombies, or (ii) the move from their ideal conceivability to their 1-possibility is disagreement with Chalmers *only* if this is not done via the adoption of Russellian monism. So when you suggest in your paper that the failure of (i) and (ii) may be due to the fact that ‘Like Leibniz we have an impoverished conception of the physical’ (p. 7), you are in no way expressing disagreement with Chalmers (probably this isn’t important, I just found it slightly confusing).
On the more important point, it seems to me that at best we just have some considerations to balance (which I don’t think Chalmers would deny). We have good reason to accept (i) and (ii), but we may also have reasons to deny (i) and (ii). What is the argument that the reasons to deny (i) and (ii) are stronger that the reasons to accept them (Or do you think we have no reason to respect a priori judgements about what is ideally conceivable, in which case what is the argument for that?)?
Moreover, I don’t see how we have *any* reason to deny (i) and (ii) given that Russellian monism allows us to make sense of the realisation of the mental in the physical without having to do so. Therefore, the balance of considerations clearly leads us to Russellian monism rather than conventional physicalism.
Sorry for not replying sooner – busy grading final exams and papers, plus a job search. I’m glad the conference has been extended a week!
Mark:
Yes, I think you’ve put your
finger on the critical issues for my position. What prior reasons do we have
for thinking that P metaphysically necessitates Q? I also need to get clear as
to who exactly is supposed to be my audience here – those who have previous
commitments to physicalism, those who are genuinely undecided, or everyone? I
really appreciate you pushing me on this – your comments are spot on. Let me at
least say something about the very helpful points you make about my 3 reasons
in favor of taking the relationship to be metaphysical necessitation rather
than nomological necessitation.
1. You say that F=ma is a
non-causal, nomological necessity, so why not think of the phenomenal
consciousness case as being like this? I admit to not knowing exactly what position
to take here. The obvious possibilities to consider are that F=ma is a causal
claim or that it is a metaphysical necessity. While I don’t think most laws of
nature are metaphysically necessary, this general law relating fundamental
concepts might be such. I’m inclined to say that F=ma is metaphysically necessary
(perhaps with the qualification that no non-alien forces are present). This is
outside my expertise, though, so I don’t know.
2. What reason do we have
for thinking this particular relation is one of metaphysical necessity rather than
just nomological necessity? I really want to push this point more than the
others. Isn’t it true that in other areas we have thought (or do think) that a
relationship is metaphysically necessary rather than nomologically necessary,
even though we don’t see why/how? We could have thought (or I do think) that the
liquidity of water is metaphysically necessitated by its chemical properties
without knowing at all how this is the case? I would challenge someone who
claimed, instead, that there is merely a nomological connection between the
chemical properties and liquidity. (To be clear, I am imagining this exchange
taking place prior to the discovery of how liquidity is realized.) Why would we
think this? Perhaps because we think there is constitutive dependence of
liquidity on the chemical, and this suggests a stronger connection than just
nomological connection. Similarly, few think that physical depends on the
phenomenal (though, of course, there are some), but it is natural to suppose
that there is a constitutive relationship in the other direction. Finally, the
metaphysical necessitation picture is simpler than the nomological
necessitation hypothesis, since it gets rid of nomological danglers – the
phenomenal is there because it (really) must be there.
3. Why rely on the past
successes of physicalism, given that consciousness is unique in not being a
structural/dynamical property (supposedly) and also being open to
introspection? I don’t have anything major or novel to say here. But gravity
seemed unique and bizarre at one time. And so did life and a host of other
phenomena that were eventually incorporated into the physical sciences.
Philip:
Yes, I grant the privileged
access we have to knowing that phenomenal concepts are satisfied. (Does this
rise to certainty? I don’t know –
probably.) But, I don’t see how it at all follows from this that we are in an
especially good position to know the essences of phenomenal kinds on a priori
grounds.
“Denying (i) the ideal
conceivability of zombies, or (ii) the move from their ideal conceivability to
their 1-possibility is disagreement with Chalmers only if this is not
done via the adoption of Russellian monism.” This is true. I take the zombie
argument to be an argument primarily for dualism, though, with the Russellian
monism thing added on as more of a caveat. Maybe I shouldn’t. Regardless, my
point here is to defend physicalism (in whatever form) by running the argument
backwards and showing that we have reason to deny either (i) or (ii) without
this being an ad hoc strong necessity.
“What is the argument that
the reasons to deny (i) and (ii) are stronger than the reasons to accept them?”
Well, this hinges on whether we have independent reasons for taking the
relationship between P and Q to be metaphysically necessary. This is critical,
of course, and it’s addressed in the discussion with Mark, above. So, I think
there are empirical reasons to think the relationship is one of realization
(understand as metaphysical necessitation), and then I run the zombie argument
backwards to explain why this isn’t an unexpected or ad hoc exception to the
general connection between conceivability and possibility.
Bence:
Yeah, I’m not a fan of a
priori input that is specific to the kind in question (as opposed to
contributing general logical/metaphysical input that is domain-neutral), unless
we are talking about math or logic (or maybe ethics). Also, I mainly had ethics
in mind (in footnote 15), when I mentioned normative kinds that are within the
domain of the a priori. I should maybe just avoid bringing this up. Ha. You
very well might be right about the relevance of empirical input to epistemic or
moral justification, say.
Thank you all for the very helpful comments!