The single alter fallacy. A critique of Bernardo Kastrup's ontology
Bernardo Kastrup’s case for idealism, as expounded most recently in his book The Idea of the World (2019) and his doctoral dissertation “Analytic Idealism: A consciousness-only ontology.” (2019), constitutes without doubt a monumental intellectual achievement, and an important contribution to contemporary philosophy. Kastrup’s arguments for idealism and against the current dominant paradigm of physicalism are so powerful and compelling that it is no longer inconceivable that idealism might displace materialism/physicalism as the dominant ontology in Western philosophy and science in the not so distant future. The urgent need for this paradigm shift, given our current civilizational and ecological crisis, endows Bernardo Kastrup’s body of work with the utmost relevance.
That said, Bernardo Kastrup’s version of idealism presents some problems that (in my view) diminish its potential as the ontology of the future. Most of these problems can be reduced to a fundamental error that we can call “the single alter fallacy”. The purpose of this essay is to elucidate this fallacy, showing its deep implications.
The single alter fallacy
In The Idea of the World, Bernardo Kastrup describes the hypothetical origin of alters in consciousness (here called TWE, “that which experiences”) in the following fashion:
“(...) before its first alter ever formed, TWE experienced only thoughts. There were no perceptions. The formation of the first alter then demarcated a boundary separating the experiences within the alter from those outside the alter (all of which were, of course, still within TWE). This newly formed boundary is what enabled perceptions to arise: the thoughts surrounding the alter stimulated its boundary from the outside, which in turn impinged on the alter’s internal dynamics.”
(Kastrup, Bernardo. The Idea of the World (p. 74). John Hunt Publishing. Kindle Edition.)
The fallacy here resides in the idea of a single alter (beginning with the “first alter”), separated by a boundary from the “outside world” (this outside world being constituted by the “thoughts” or non-dissociated experiences of TWE or “cosmic consciousness”). In reality, it is not possible to have a single alter. Alters can only exist as a multiplicity. The minimum number is two. Either there are multiple alters, or there is none.
The crucial point is this: the boundary that demarcates an alter doesn’t separate it from a hypothetical “outside world” (there is no such thing as an outside world), but from other alters. All boundaries are boundaries between alters.
Like Bernardo Kastrup explains, without alters there can be no perceptions. Before the formation of alters there were only thoughts (following Bernardo Kastrup’s terminology, the word “thought” refers here to any experience distinct from perception), the thoughts of the unified, non-dissociated consciousness. Only when consciousness divided itself in two, giving rise to the first two alters, did perceptions arise.
The only difference between thoughts and perceptions is that thoughts are private, while perceptions are collective. The thoughts of Alter 1 and Alter 2 are independent of each other, but the perceptions of Alter 1 and Alter 2 are connected: borrowing a term from quantum physics, we can say that the perceptions of all alters are entangled.
Let’s try to imagine a single alter. Could this single alter have perceptions? The only way we can carry out this thought experiment is by imagining that we are that single alter. So, let’s say that I am the only alter in the universe, and that right now I’m experiencing myself as a man walking through a forest. I can see the trees, insects, birds, maybe a deer, but none of those are alters. They don’t have consciousness. I am the only one who is experiencing this forest. Is this experience different from a dream? No, it isn’t. I am having a dream. I am not perceiving anything. That forest exists only in my mind. All my experiences of this forest are thoughts. This simply means that I am not really an alter. I may experience myself as a man in a forest, but both the forest and the man are just thoughts in my mind.
But let’s imagine that I decide to dissociate myself, to split my consciousness into two. As I walk through the forest I suddenly encounter another human being. Let’s say this other being is a woman. And she too has consciousness. She experiences the forest too, from a different point of view. All our experiences are consistent. If I see a rock here, or a tree, or a pond, she sees it too. And vice versa. Now we are having perceptions. She and I are dissociated alters.
This simple thought experiment shows that it is necessary to have at least two alters for perceptions to arise. We can say that dissociation of consciousness into at least two different points of view (alters) is what gave rise to the physical world in the first place.
Having explained this “single alter fallacy”, we can now analyse its far-reaching implications. Closely connected to the erroneous notion of a single alter are two other fallacies, both deeply ingrained in Bernardo Kastrup’s ontology: we can call them the “local fallacy” and the “second-person fallacy”.
The local fallacy
In Bernardo Kastrup’s view, as we have seen, the boundaries that demarcate alters create a separation between the experiences within the alters and the experiences outside them. This distinction between inner and outer experiences implies the idea that alters are localized bubbles of dissociated consciousness surrounded by non-dissociated consciousness (“mind-at-large”). In other words, consciousness is imagined as a sort of space in which alters exist. Different alters are located in different points of this space, in the same way as in classical (Newtonian) physics material objects were thought to be located in an absolute three-dimensional space.
In this view, which we can call “local idealism”, alters are seen as disconnected from each other. Their perceptions of the physical world are caused by the thoughts of a hypothetical non-dissociated cosmic consciousness or “mind-at-large”. This universal mind surrounds and contains alters in the same way as in physicalism the physical world is supposed to contain material objects, including conscious observers.
In reality, there is no such thing as a non-dissociated universal mind or “mind-at-large”. This “mind-at-large” is nothing but an explanatory abstraction. Kastrup falls into the same error he accurately points out as the fundamental fallacy of physicalism: to postulate the existence of a hypothetical objective reality “out there”, as the explanation for a) the fact that we all seem to perceive the same world and b) the regularity and consistency of our perceptions. Kastrup goes as far as to propose that the laws of physics are the thoughts of this hypothetical non-dissociated universal consciousness. This error is a direct result of the single alter fallacy.
Once we realize that dissociation is nothing but the split of consciousness into a multiplicity of alters, we can see that we don’t need any explanatory abstractions (no notions of an objective reality existing outside our experience) to account for the aforementioned facts. We all perceive the same world simply because we are dissociated alters of the same consciousness. Our separation is only relative and apparent: it exists only on the level of perceptions. On a deeper level, we are one. We are one consciousness. The regularity and consistency of our perceptions (the laws of physics) are the result of the simple fact that we all are dreaming the same collective dream. We are constantly creating the physical world with our perceptions. These perceptions have to be mutually consistent in order for us to dream the same dream. If that consistency failed, we would fall into the realm of individual dreams or hallucinations. Our individual perceptions constantly influence and interact with each other. This is what physicists call entanglement. The laws of physics are the laws of perception. Perception is entangled experience.
Figure 4: The world according to nonlocal idealism. The perceptions of all alters are entangled.
We can call this view “nonlocal idealism”. In nonlocal idealism, there is no notion of a world “out there”. There is no distinction between “inner” and “outer” experiences. All experiences happen in consciousness. Consciousness has no spatial qualities. Space exists only on the level of perception. The only difference between our thoughts (dreams, fantasies, philosophical abstractions, etc.) and our perceptions of the physical world is that our perceptions are entangled with the perceptions of all other alters. The physical world is nothing but our perceptions. We don’t need to postulate any “objective” (and essentially unknowable) reality outside our perceptions to explain the regularity and consistency of these. Entanglement, which is not an explanatory abstraction but an observable fact, provides sufficient explanation.
The second-person fallacy
The last fallacy we are going to discuss in this short essay is the idea that consciousness can be experienced from a second-person perspective. In Bernardo Kastrup’s analytic idealism (or local idealism, as it could accurately be called), when an alter (A1) perceives the body of another alter (A2), A1 is having an “extrinsic view of the inner experiences of A2”. In other words, A1 is having a second-person experience of the first-person experiences of A2.
Figure 5: The second-person fallacy (Kastrup, 2019, "Analytic Idealism")
This notion is obviously absurd. It is not possible to have conscious experiences from a second-person perspective. Consciousness can only be experienced from a first-person perspective.
We can see this clearly if we recall the Mars rover metaphor. When we see the Mars rover, we are not seeing in any way the conscious experiences of the scientists using the rover to explore Mars. Analogously, when we see the bodies of other conscious beings we don’t perceive their conscious experiences. We just perceive their bodies, which are part of the physical world, and therefore consist solely of first-person perceptions (the entangled perceptions of all alters perceiving those bodies, including the alters that inhabit them). There is no such thing as the extrinsic appearance of a conscious experience.
We may infer the inner experiences of another human being by looking at the expression of their faces (we can’t do the same with plants and most animals), but that’s only a logical deduction. We may also experience states of deep connection with other human beings, in which we feel we share their emotions. These are instances in which the dissociative boundaries between alters become transparent and we get glimpses of the underlying oneness. All these experiences are only accessible from a first-person perspective.
It is important to remember that alters are not part of the physical world. There is no such thing as the extrinsic appearance of an alter. Alters perceive, but they can’t be perceived. Alters are dissociations of consciousness, and as such, exist only as consciousness. The physical world exists inside alters (in the form of perceptions), not the other way round.
Nonlocal Idealism
As we have shown, nonlocal idealism (the view proposed in this essay) is more parsimonious than Bernardo Kastrup’s analytic (or local) idealism. In nonlocal idealism we don’t add any explanatory abstractions (like a hypothetical non-dissociated universal consciousness or “mind-at-large” whose thoughts are the cause of the laws of nature and of all our perceptions) to the only empirical facts about the physical world: our own perceptions.
It remains to be seen how nonlocal idealism compares with local idealism in terms of explanatory power. We have already shown that nonlocal idealism explains in a parsimonious, elegant manner two of the basic facts which traditionally have been considered the most powerful arguments in favour of physicalism: a) the fact that we all seem to inhabit the same world, and b) the fact that the physical world behaves in a regular, predictable fashion, independent from our personal volition.
Let’s briefly consider these two facts again. According to nonlocal idealism, the physical world is a collective dream. We are constantly creating it with our perceptions. The reason why we all perceive the same world, why we all share the same dream, is that underneath our superficial dissociation we are all one: we are one consciousness.
As for the regularity and predictability of the physical world (in other words, of our perceptions), it is accounted for by the fact that this world is a shared dream. All regularities in nature can be deduced from the fundamental entanglement of all conscious observers (alters), including all living organisms. Entanglement also explains why our perceptions are independent from our personal volition. The laws of perception (i.e., the laws of physics) are the necessary condition for the existence of the collective dream (i.e., the physical world). On a fundamental level, these laws are the result of nonlocal entanglement.
Let’s examine now a third fact that is often proposed as evidence for physicalism: the correlation between brain activity and inner experience. From the perspective of nonlocal idealism, this correlation can be explained quite simply. Our brains, like the rest of our bodies, are physical objects. As such, they are the result of billions of years of evolution constrained by the laws of perception (the laws of physics). Our nervous system, which includes our sense organs and our brain, enables our consciousness to perceive the collective dream (the physical world) in particular ways. Our sense organs and brains don’t generate our perceptions, but they act as a conduit for them. Our eyes and visual cortex, for example, play the same role as the cameras and radio transmitters on a Mars rover. The actual experience of seeing doesn’t happen in the brain (in the same way that no experience happens inside the Mars rover), but in consciousness. Our bodies, including our brains, function as an interface between our consciousness and the physical world.
When it comes to thoughts (experiences distinct from perceptions), we can safely say that the brain doesn’t generate thoughts (or any other experience), but that it does generate the content of those thoughts. We can hypothesize, for example, that the same brain areas that function as a transmitting interface between our sense organs and our consciousness can generate visual and other sensory images during dreams, hallucinations or visualizations. The crucial point is that the brain generates or arranges the content of our conscious experiences, but not the experiences themselves. The experiencing awareness is a quality of consciousness, which is the fundamental and ultimate reality, the ontological primitive.
This may sound as a kind of dualism, but since we have defined the physical world (which includes brains) as the sum of the perceptions of all alters, we can see that we are not contradicting in any way our monistic, idealistic ontology. Our brains are nothing but a very sophisticated arrangement of conscious perceptions, the result of billions of years of evolution, as part of this vast experiment in dissociated experience or collective dreaming created by consciousness, this amazing research project we call the physical universe.
In reality, it is not possible to have a single alter. Alters can only exist as a multiplicity. The minimum number is two. Either there are multiple alters, or there is none.
The only difference between thoughts and perceptions is that thoughts are private, while perceptions are collective.
Let’s try to imagine a single alter. Could this single alter have perceptions? The only way we can carry out this thought experiment is by imagining that we are that single alter. So, let’s say that I am the only alter in the universe, and that right now I’m experiencing myself as a man walking through a forest. I can see the trees, insects, birds, maybe a deer, but none of those are alters. They don’t have consciousness. I am the only one who is experiencing this forest. Is this experience different from a dream? No, it isn’t. I am having a dream. I am not perceiving anything. That forest exists only in my mind. All my experiences of this forest are thoughts. This simply means that I am not really an alter. I may experience myself as a man in a forest, but both the forest and the man are just thoughts in my mind.
In reality, there is no such thing as a non-dissociated universal mind or “mind-at-large”. This “mind-at-large” is nothing but an explanatory abstraction. Kastrup falls into the same error he accurately points out as the fundamental fallacy of physicalism
We all perceive the same world simply because we are dissociated alters of the same consciousness.
The regularity and consistency of our perceptions (the laws of physics) are the result of the simple fact that we all are dreaming the same collective dream.
The last fallacy we are going to discuss in this short essay is the idea that consciousness can be experienced from a second-person perspective. ... This notion is obviously absurd. It is not possible to have conscious experiences from a second-person perspective. Consciousness can only be experienced from a first-person perspective.
Hi Adur,In reality, it is not possible to have a single alter. Alters can only exist as a multiplicity. The minimum number is two. Either there are multiple alters, or there is none.Yes, but that is a trivial issue of terminology. 'Mind at large' is, technically, also an alter, though at a completely different scale. So I reserved the use of the word 'alter' to the scale of living creatures. But, again, mind-at-large is technically an alter.
The only difference between thoughts and perceptions is that thoughts are private, while perceptions are collective.Not really. 'Thoughts,' as the word is used in this part of the book, are endogenous, arising within the dissociative boundary of the respective alter (or mind-at-large). Perceptions, on the other hand, are triggered by experiential states beyond the boundary of the respective alter. They are not defined in terms of consensus at all.
Let’s try to imagine a single alter. Could this single alter have perceptions? The only way we can carry out this thought experiment is by imagining that we are that single alter. So, let’s say that I am the only alter in the universe, and that right now I’m experiencing myself as a man walking through a forest. I can see the trees, insects, birds, maybe a deer, but none of those are alters. They don’t have consciousness. I am the only one who is experiencing this forest. Is this experience different from a dream? No, it isn’t. I am having a dream. I am not perceiving anything. That forest exists only in my mind. All my experiences of this forest are thoughts. This simply means that I am not really an alter. I may experience myself as a man in a forest, but both the forest and the man are just thoughts in my mind.Clearly I lost you in my argument. If there is an alter there is also mind-at-large (i.e. a second, 'very big alter'), or the rest of universal consciousness beyond the dissociative boundary of the one alter. My perceptions would then correspond to experiential states of mind-at-large. I would see no living beings (no birds or trees), only an inanimate universe. Now, you can argue that such an 'inanimate' universe is just another, unfathomably huge 'alter.' That would be correct, but also trivial in the context of the argument. I just use the word 'alter' at a given scale, for ease of discourse.
In reality, there is no such thing as a non-dissociated universal mind or “mind-at-large”. This “mind-at-large” is nothing but an explanatory abstraction. Kastrup falls into the same error he accurately points out as the fundamental fallacy of physicalismThis seems like an entirely arbitrary statement to me.
We all perceive the same world simply because we are dissociated alters of the same consciousness.Yes, indeed. This is what I say...The regularity and consistency of our perceptions (the laws of physics) are the result of the simple fact that we all are dreaming the same collective dream.The only interpretation of this that would make it different from what I am claiming is this: at a deeper level we are all connected, like branches of a single tree, and a dream is broadcast to each branch from the root of tree, so to speak, with some perspectival adjustments. This doesn't work for reasons I discuss in the 'closing commentary' of the book: it cannot explain why we see other alters around. If each of us is a TV to which a common 'dream' is broadcast, why to we see representations of other TVs within our dream? The broadcast idea implies one-way communication from the root of consciousness to the branches. But clearly we see other alters around ourselves as well. If, in turn, you say that communication is actually two-way and can happen locally, then the whole thing will boil down to what I am saying already, even if you prefer a different metaphor for it.
The last fallacy we are going to discuss in this short essay is the idea that consciousness can be experienced from a second-person perspective. ... This notion is obviously absurd. It is not possible to have conscious experiences from a second-person perspective. Consciousness can only be experienced from a first-person perspective.Oh well. Here you seem to be ignoring my explanations. Each time I see, touch and talk to my girlfriend I am experiencing her conscious inner-life from a second-person perspective, in the sense I explain it: what I see, hear and touch are the extrinsic appearance of her inner states, as conveyed to me through mind-at-large. To deny that when I see, talk and touch to another human being I am interacting, indirectly, with the other person's conscious inner life is obviously false.
Anyway, I understand the rest of your essay follows from the arguments I commented on above, so I will stop here.I'd encourage you to read my material again.Cheers, Bernardo.
"My point is that, once dissociation happens, mind-at-large (non-dissociated universal consciousness) ceases to exist."
1) In your opinion, what is it that dissociates?
2) if that (this things that dissociates) becomes unstable and dissaptes, you think there is then absolutely nothing?
For me, the substrate as MaL makes sense of all the "play" of dissociation that can come and go, all arising and fading within MaL.
Thanks
Jeff
Thanks for responding so quickly, Bernardo!I went back and re-read the "Closing commentary" of The Idea of the World. I must admit I had skipped the section called "Alternative formulations of dissociation-based idealism" because I thought it was a literal reproduction of the section under the same title in your dissertation, which I had already read. Thus, I had missed this sentence: "I have taken the trouble to explore this defunct formulation here for the following reason: in my experience, many intelligent people who hear the idealist adage ‘reality is akin to a collective dream’ try to construe its meaning along the general outline of this formulation." This, combined with the questions some of the professors made during your defense, gives me the reassuring impression that I may be into something here... it also makes me feel that I'm one of those "intelligent people"! HahaThat said, I don't feel you really responded to my objections here, but the reason is that I'm sure I didn't make my points sufficiently clear. So, let me explain myself better: I am not denying the inner consistency and explanatory power of your ontology. As I said, I think it's a monumental achievement. I simply feel that it isn't convincing enough to turn the tables. I didn't make this clear in my "essay", but my purpose is only to point out why I think your ontology isn't convincing enough, and to suggest a more viable (in my opinion, of course) alternative.By the way, from your defense video I got the impression that the professors weren't convinced either, but that they certainly were impressed. In any case, that's what I feel. I just think that with a little tweaking your ontology would not only be impressive in its scope and depth, but also more compelling.I will respond to your comments below.
On Thursday, 2 May 2019 12:07:33 UTC+2, Bernardo wrote:Hi Adur,In reality, it is not possible to have a single alter. Alters can only exist as a multiplicity. The minimum number is two. Either there are multiple alters, or there is none.Yes, but that is a trivial issue of terminology. 'Mind at large' is, technically, also an alter, though at a completely different scale. So I reserved the use of the word 'alter' to the scale of living creatures. But, again, mind-at-large is technically an alter.I don't think this is a trivial question. What I'm saying is that there is no mind-at-large. My point is that, once dissociation happens, mind-at-large (non-dissociated universal consciousness) ceases to exist. I remember you saying in your thesis defense that in DID cases there seems to be a "host personality". I don't know if that's the case, and I'm not sure what it means (what is the difference between the host personality and the other alters?), but there is a fundamental difference between alters and mind-at-large, isn't it? Saying that mind-at-large is technically an alter is a trivial use of terminology, though! The question here is: does mind-at-large exist?
The only difference between thoughts and perceptions is that thoughts are private, while perceptions are collective.Not really. 'Thoughts,' as the word is used in this part of the book, are endogenous, arising within the dissociative boundary of the respective alter (or mind-at-large). Perceptions, on the other hand, are triggered by experiential states beyond the boundary of the respective alter. They are not defined in terms of consensus at all.I perfectly understand how you define perceptions, as opposed to thoughts. I am just proposing a different definition here. Note that your definition rests on the idea of the existence of mind-at-large. If there is no mind-at-large. and if there are only dissociated alters (that's the view I'm proposing) there is nothing beyond the boundary of an alter but other alters.
Let’s try to imagine a single alter. Could this single alter have perceptions? The only way we can carry out this thought experiment is by imagining that we are that single alter. So, let’s say that I am the only alter in the universe, and that right now I’m experiencing myself as a man walking through a forest. I can see the trees, insects, birds, maybe a deer, but none of those are alters. They don’t have consciousness. I am the only one who is experiencing this forest. Is this experience different from a dream? No, it isn’t. I am having a dream. I am not perceiving anything. That forest exists only in my mind. All my experiences of this forest are thoughts. This simply means that I am not really an alter. I may experience myself as a man in a forest, but both the forest and the man are just thoughts in my mind.Clearly I lost you in my argument. If there is an alter there is also mind-at-large (i.e. a second, 'very big alter'), or the rest of universal consciousness beyond the dissociative boundary of the one alter. My perceptions would then correspond to experiential states of mind-at-large. I would see no living beings (no birds or trees), only an inanimate universe. Now, you can argue that such an 'inanimate' universe is just another, unfathomably huge 'alter.' That would be correct, but also trivial in the context of the argument. I just use the word 'alter' at a given scale, for ease of discourse.You are right, Bernardo, I can see now that my thought experiment doesn't work within the parameters of your definition of alters. Given your definition of what an alter is, a single alter would only witness an inanimate universe. Still, I can't see in what meaningful way a single alter surrounded by an inanimate universe would be an alter.
Let's say this alter is watching stars. Where is the dissociation?
You need to postulate from the beginning that stars are the extrinsic appearance of something else, something we can't even begin to imagine, the inner life of this hypothetical mind-at-large.
So, even if my thought experiment doesn't work as such, I think it serves to show that my definition of alters is more intuitive and parsimonious.
I can't imagine that mysterious mind-at-large, or how and why dissociation began. If you are correct, and mind-at-large exists, its inner experience is fundamentally different from ours. If I'm correct, the primordial non-dissociated consciousness would be essentially identical to ours. This primordial consciousness would have dreams, like we do, and at some point would decide to dissociate itself into different alters, different points of view, just to make the dream more interesting... Alan Watts has some beautiful talks about this kind of idea. Some may find it naive, but it makes sense. Contrary to what some scientists seem to think, I believe that an intuitive theory is always preferable to a counter-intuitive one, especially if it works better and is more consistent with the empirical facts!
In reality, there is no such thing as a non-dissociated universal mind or “mind-at-large”. This “mind-at-large” is nothing but an explanatory abstraction. Kastrup falls into the same error he accurately points out as the fundamental fallacy of physicalismThis seems like an entirely arbitrary statement to me.Well, again, I was being deliberately provocative. But given that we have no direct experience of this mind-at--large (we have no idea how it is like to be that mind-at-large), I think it's just that: an explanatory abstraction.
I completely agree with you in that consciousness is the ontological primitive and the most basic fact in our expereince, but this mind-at-large is only an abstraction. Can you explain to me why you think it isn't?
We all perceive the same world simply because we are dissociated alters of the same consciousness.Yes, indeed. This is what I say...The regularity and consistency of our perceptions (the laws of physics) are the result of the simple fact that we all are dreaming the same collective dream.The only interpretation of this that would make it different from what I am claiming is this: at a deeper level we are all connected, like branches of a single tree, and a dream is broadcast to each branch from the root of tree, so to speak, with some perspectival adjustments. This doesn't work for reasons I discuss in the 'closing commentary' of the book: it cannot explain why we see other alters around. If each of us is a TV to which a common 'dream' is broadcast, why to we see representations of other TVs within our dream? The broadcast idea implies one-way communication from the root of consciousness to the branches. But clearly we see other alters around ourselves as well. If, in turn, you say that communication is actually two-way and can happen locally, then the whole thing will boil down to what I am saying already, even if you prefer a different metaphor for it.I claim that there is another possible interpretation: yes, we are all connected on a deeper level (I think true emotions like love and compassion arise from that deeper level), but the dream is not generated on that deep level. The collective dream is co-created simultaneously by all alters. Communication is not two-way, but "zillions-way": it happens between all alters.
But given that we have no direct experience of this mind-at--large (we have no idea how it is like to be that mind-at-large), I think it's just that: an explanatory abstraction.
Surely many mystics, adepts of deep meditation practice, and even users of certain entheogens, would make the case that there are ways to glimpse such a state, call it nondual, primordial Awareness -- albeit it ultimately defies any languaging of it, and as mentioned earlier there is no exclusive abidance as such a state.
There is abidance ...I said no exclusive abidance, and was referring to a state such as whatever state Ramana was in -- voidness? -- prior to leaving the caves, wherein he was so utterly immersed in that state that he never spoke, and was oblivious to any corporeal concerns, and from which state, short of corporeal death, he eventually had to emerge and interact again with the world and others ...
Lou ... Sure, but in this thread, in strict ontological terms, I just meant that M@L can only ever succumb to its immanent, imperative, self-perpetual dynamic of self-excitaion/individuation.
Brief comments in bold below. Cheers, B.
I don't think this is a trivial question. What I'm saying is that there is no mind-at-large. My point is that, once dissociation happens, mind-at-large (non-dissociated universal consciousness) ceases to exist. I remember you saying in your thesis defense that in DID cases there seems to be a "host personality". I don't know if that's the case, and I'm not sure what it means (what is the difference between the host personality and the other alters?), but there is a fundamental difference between alters and mind-at-large, isn't it? Saying that mind-at-large is technically an alter is a trivial use of terminology, though! The question here is: does mind-at-large exist?You are disputing word definitions. I define mind-at-large as the segment of universal consciousness that remains outside all life-scale alters. As such, it obviously exists. Is it an alter? Technically it is, but at another scale. A host personality is itself also an 'alter,' technically, but it is the more encompassing alter and the one into which all alters collapse if DID ends. So we distinguish it linguistically by calling it 'host personality,' instead of 'alter.'
The only difference between thoughts and perceptions is that thoughts are private, while perceptions are collective.Not really. 'Thoughts,' as the word is used in this part of the book, are endogenous, arising within the dissociative boundary of the respective alter (or mind-at-large). Perceptions, on the other hand, are triggered by experiential states beyond the boundary of the respective alter. They are not defined in terms of consensus at all.I perfectly understand how you define perceptions, as opposed to thoughts. I am just proposing a different definition here. Note that your definition rests on the idea of the existence of mind-at-large. If there is no mind-at-large. and if there are only dissociated alters (that's the view I'm proposing) there is nothing beyond the boundary of an alter but other alters.As I define it, mind-atlarge exists, for trivial reasons.
You are right, Bernardo, I can see now that my thought experiment doesn't work within the parameters of your definition of alters. Given your definition of what an alter is, a single alter would only witness an inanimate universe. Still, I can't see in what meaningful way a single alter surrounded by an inanimate universe would be an alter.It's dissociated from its surroundings. That's what defines a life-scale alter.Let's say this alter is watching stars. Where is the dissociation?In the very fact that it is watching stars. Otherwise, there would be no perception. The 'stars' would be directly evoked, endogenous ideas.You need to postulate from the beginning that stars are the extrinsic appearance of something else, something we can't even begin to imagine, the inner life of this hypothetical mind-at-large.That's precisely the point. It's a postulate--rather an inference--with significant explanatory power and parsimoniously anchored on empirical facts: my own inner ideas appear to others as my 'material' brain activity, which is qualitatively different from how the inner ideas feel to me. So the inner ideas of mind-at-large appear to us as the 'material,' inanimate universe around us, although they feel differently to mind-at-large itself.
Well, again, I was being deliberately provocative. But given that we have no direct experience of this mind-at--large (we have no idea how it is like to be that mind-at-large), I think it's just that: an explanatory abstraction.
Only insofar as my belief that your conscious inner life is also an explanatory abstraction; or that the conscious inner life of my cats, or of the bacteria in my toilet, are also explanatory abstractions. If you are skeptical of that, solipsism is your only option.
I completely agree with you in that consciousness is the ontological primitive and the most basic fact in our expereince, but this mind-at-large is only an abstraction. Can you explain to me why you think it isn't?If you deny the conscious inner-life of mind-at-large, you either deny any form of noumena to make sense of the regularities of perceptual experience; or you need some arbitrary discontinuity in your model.
I claim that there is another possible interpretation: yes, we are all connected on a deeper level (I think true emotions like love and compassion arise from that deeper level), but the dream is not generated on that deep level. The collective dream is co-created simultaneously by all alters. Communication is not two-way, but "zillions-way": it happens between all alters.Then, and assuming that you don't deny the existence of an inanimate universe surrounding life, you need a surrounding mental substrate to enable the communication; i.e. mind-at-large. You may be imaging it in a different 'shape' then my schematics of mind-at-large, but if you make explicit what you are imaging, and look at its topology, you will see that it is entirely equivalent to mind-at-large. Otherwise, you end up with an arbitrary discontinuity: the matter in our bodies is the image of inner life, but the matter in the inanimate universe is, ontologically, something completely different and purely imagined, even though it is the same matter; so much so that the matter in our bodies even becomes part of the inanimate universe upon our deaths (and even during life, with secretion).
Jeff
In a nutshell, my disagreement with Bernardo can be reduced to a disagreement with this statement, which Bernardo himself identifies as the foundation of his entire system (he says so at the beginning of his "Closing commentary"): matter is the outer appearance of inner experience. I completely disagree with this. I think that the idea of outer or extrinsic appearances is incompatible with idealism.
In a nutshell, my disagreement with Bernardo can be reduced to a disagreement with this statement, which Bernardo himself identifies as the foundation of his entire system (he says so at the beginning of his "Closing commentary"): matter is the outer appearance of inner experience. I completely disagree with this. I think that the idea of outer or extrinsic appearances is incompatible with idealism.An appearance is itself an experience, purely mental. So this isn't incompatible with idealism at all. But okay, you disagree that matter is how experience looks like from across a dissociative boundary. How, then, do you explain the tight correlations between inner experience and brain activity? How do you explain that, if you add alcohol to the chemistry of your brain, your inner experience changes? How do you explain that trauma to the head changes experience? How do you explain that your body is the immediate manifestation of your inner life, or the 'bodying-forth' of inner experience?
My issue is with the qualifier outer or extrinsic. All experience is intrinsic. How can there be extrinsic experiences?
But Bernardo carefully has addressed the exact point you worry about.
On another note, you actually speak of the brain as an object that interacts with experience.
I'm with Bernardo here in seeing the brain as a partial image of consciousness, not entity interacting with it.
I don't think I agree with that definition of volitional. I feel comfortable saying that my dog uses volition to get through the blankets or to eat his food.
For me, and others, volition and experience go hand in hand. Yet, I acknowledge there is a wide spectrum whereupon both extremes may appear very different.
One thing I've noticed as I study more and more ontological systems, is that arguments about the definition of words never stops.
However, things get most interesting when even people who disagree are noticing and respecting the different uses of words. that's when the conversation can move from pure semantic-image land.
I'm not holding up my understanding of volition as the right one. I fully understand how it could be carved out so that volition should only be used when describing abstract and highly cognitive behaviors.
Volitional means voluntary, or done by an act of will. It refers to something intentional, premeditated, deliberate, conscious.
done by conscious, personal choice; not based on external principles.
Volition or will is the cognitive process by which an individual decides on and commits to a particular course of action. It is defined as purposive striving and is one of the primary human psychological functions.
Many of us just see no evidence that the brain is something interacting at all with experience. So far you've pointed to nothing that shifts me from seeing it as a partial image of another alter's inner process.
Lou ... Good points. I certainly don't consider my path a typical case study -- indeed I may be as rare as Leopardus Guttulus . And even with the finding of a compelling model, as of yet a work in progress, there is still a healing process going on, and the supporting model is more just a permission slip to embrace that process within the context of the primacy of consciousness. How it will play out in any other cases, through whichever combination of experiential revelation, compelling model, and healing, not necessarily in that order, I'll have to leave to The Great Mysteriousness :)
Bernardo, I know quite well what I'm saying, although it's obvious that I'm not expressing myself clearly.
The thing is, I can assure you that I understand your system perfectly. I understand what you mean by extrinsic appearance, when you say that matter is the extrinsic appearance of inner expereince. It is an ingenious idea, and it makes sense on a superficial level. I simply don't think it ultimately works.