转一篇文章,来自
http://www.moreintelligentlife.com/content/ideas/anthony-gottlieb/what-do-philosophers-believe
============================
From INTELLIGENT LIFE Magazine, Spring 2010
There was once a website on which academic philosophers listed the
curious things that strangers had said to them upon learning that they
were in the presence of a philosopher. The following conversation
allegedly took place on an aeroplane:
“May I ask you a question?”
“Yes.”
“It’s a philosophical question. Is that ok?”
“Sure.”
“There’s a boy I fancy. Should I text him or e-mail him?”
In a similar vein, also from the skies:
“What do you do?”
“I’m a philosopher.”
“What are some of your sayings, then?”
This exchange makes professional philosophers titter, because their
daily work is far removed from the production of sage utterances. But
the request for “sayings” was not an unreasonable one. The great
philosophers of old are remembered largely by their posthumous
contributions to dictionaries of quotations. How is an ordinary person
to know what today’s professional philosophers think?
One answer – a novel one, it seems – comes from a new survey of
philosophers’ views. A preliminary analysis of the results has been
published in an electronic journal,
PhilPapers. Unfortunately, however,
the survey was written for philosophy nerds. So here is a translation
for airline passengers.
First, some background. The questions are geared to what’s known as
the “analytical” type of philosophy, which now dominates university
philosophy departments in the West and almost monopolises those in
English-speaking countries. The pioneers of this movement, which first
took root in Britain in the first half of the 20th century, include
Bertrand Russell and Ludwig Wittgenstein. It is a broad church nowadays,
but on the whole, analytical philosophy models its approach on the
natural sciences. Researchers, sometimes working more or less in teams,
divide problems into small pieces and try out different solutions to
them one by one. The writings of the analytical school combine
plain-speaking with technical terms that are precisely defined in the
style of scientific terminology (or at least, they are supposed to be).
This movement is often contrasted with “Continental” philosophy,
which is more expansive and synoptic, tends to see itself as allied to
literary, cultural and social studies, and is more likely to draw on
subjective experience. The big names of “Continental” philosophy are
mostly French (Sartre, Derrida, Foucault) or German (Heidegger), but the
term is doubly misleading. Many of the founders of analytical
philosophy came from continental Europe, too; and the stronghold of
“Continental” philosophy nowadays is in fact in literary and cultural
studies departments in Britain and America.
The PhilPapers study, by David Chalmers of the Australian National
University and David Bourget of London University, surveyed academics at
99 leading philosophy departments around the globe, over 90% of them in
the English-speaking world and nearly two-thirds in America. Some 91%
of the respondents thought they belonged to the analytic tradition and
4% the “Continental” one. When asked which dead philosopher they most
identified with, a clear winner emerged, with 21% of the votes: David
Hume, the 18th-century thinker, historian, sceptic and agnostic who was a
close friend of the economist Adam Smith. Aristotle, Kant and
Wittgenstein took second, third and fourth places. The next six spots
went to philosophers from the 20th century, most recently Donald
Davidson, an American who died in 2003. Plato made 13th place and
Socrates limped in at 21st.
Of the three topics that Immanuel Kant once said were the proper
subjects of metaphysics – namely God, freedom and immortality – the
survey covers only the first two, perhaps because these days life is too
short to bother with immortality. Free will gets a thumbs-up: only 12%
of philosophers think that people’s lives are predestined. But God gets
the thumbs-down: nearly three-quarters accept or lean towards atheism.
This is only to be expected. Even in America, which is unusually
religious for a rich country, the top echelons of those who think for a
living tend to be unbelievers. A survey of the members of America’s
elite National Academy of Sciences in 1998 found that only 7% believed
in God.
A quarter of a century ago, such a survey would have had plenty of
questions about language, but now there are only three (out of 30).
Analytical philosophy has shifted its attention from language to the
mind, which is why there is a question about zombies – though nothing
about ghouls, demons or vampires. By a “zombie”, today’s philosophers
mean a hypothetical being who is physically indistinguishable from a
normal person but is not conscious. Philosophers argue about whether or
not such a creature could exist in theory, and on the whole they are
pretty undecided about it. A small majority endorse “physicalism” about
the mind, which is the theory that all mental states are in fact
physical states. Many of the pioneers of the 20th-century version of
this view hailed from Australia, which led one philosophical wag to
surmise that Australia is the only country in which it is true.
Contrary to a widespread caricature, it emerges that most
philosophers do not go around doubting the existence of physical objects
(and thus colliding with them). Some 82% of the respondents accept or
are inclined towards “non-sceptical realism” about the external world,
which means they believe both that physical objects exist independently
of the minds that perceive them, and that we can be said to know of
their existence. Some 4.8%, though, are inclined to deny that we have
certain knowledge of the existence of physical objects, and 4.2% accept
or lean towards “idealism”, which is the theory that matter somehow
depends on mind. As for the status of so-called “abstract” objects, such
as numbers, the most popular view (scoring 39%, narrowly ahead of its
closest rival) is “Platonism”, according to which abstract objects have a
real existence independently of our minds.
By a fairly narrow margin, today’s philosophers believe that
judgments of artistic value are not merely matters of individual taste:
41% said aesthetic values are objective, 34% say subjective, and a
quarter gave some other answer. They were not asked directly whether
moral values are objective, but the responses to related questions
suggest that most philosophers believe they are. Some 56% incline
towards “moral realism”, which has no precise definition but implies
that ethical questions have objectively right (and wrong) answers, and
nearly two-thirds endorsed moral “cognitivism”, which suggests that they
believe there are moral facts or truths. The results reveal little
about political views, as the one question about politics is unhelpfully
phrased. Respondents were asked to choose between egalitarianism
(34.7%), communitarianism (14.2%) and libertarianism (9.8%); over 40%
were unwilling to choose for one reason or another.
In five other questions 15% or more of the philosophers said they
were too unfamiliar with the issue to give an opinion. Philosophy is now
a highly specialised discipline. A don working on, say, ethics, may not
even know the terminology used by logicians, and vice versa. This will
be grist to the mill of those who feel that analytical philosophy has
given up dealing with the big questions of life and is now mired in
technical minutiae. But not so fast. Even Plato was attacked in his own
time for treating philosophy as if it were all mathematics. And 1,800
years ago the great doctor Galen moaned about “the over-refined
linguistic quibbling of some philosophers”.
People have always wanted philosophers to provide digestible
wisdom, yet it is as true now as it was in Plato’s time that disciplined
thinking is hard. So next time you sit next to a philosopher on a
plane, talk about the movie, not the meaning of life.
(Anthony
Gottlieb is a visiting scholar at New York University and a former
executive editor of The Economist. He is also the author of
author of "The Dream of Reason: A History of Philosophy from the
Greeks to the Renaissance".)