Bohmian mechanics v Everett-DeWiit-Wheeler?For Carroll, it probably means they're the same. Indistinguishable.Ok, scratch that off the physics bucket list.
> Bohmian mechanics v Everett-DeWiit-Wheeler?For Carroll, it probably means they're the same. Indistinguishable.
--
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups "Everything List" group.
To unsubscribe from this group and stop receiving emails from it, send an email to everything-li...@googlegroups.com.
To view this discussion visit https://groups.google.com/d/msgid/everything-list/CAJPayv3JL9f40jD-4qG0ry6z38ZtVysrh9RhE%2BDirJrSWzaX-w%40mail.gmail.com.
The fundamental absurdity of single-history frameworks becomes clear when we consider the reliance on theoretical constructs that, by definition, never exist and never will. How can one justify using mathematical tools that invoke nonexistent possibilities to explain a reality where only one sequence of events is ever realized? If something never existed, has no causal influence, and will never exist in any possible future, how does it play any role in explaining what does exist?
This contradiction is evident in interpretations like Bohmian mechanics, where the pilot wave guides particles but remains completely unobservable and uninteractive beyond that role. It’s an invisible, untouchable entity that affects matter but is never affected in return—something that is functionally indistinguishable from the pure abstractions of probability waves in a single-world interpretation. In both cases, explanations rely on constructs that have no true existence beyond their mathematical form.
A single-history universe that leans on unrealized possibilities to justify probability
is making an implicit appeal to something that doesn’t and will never exist. It treats the wavefunction as a real tool for calculating outcomes while simultaneously denying that the alternatives it describes have any grounding in reality. This is the absurdity: how can something that never existed be part of an explanation for what does?
In contrast, in a many-worlds framework, all possibilities exist and are real branches of the wavefunction, providing an actual basis for probability. The probabilities are not just mathematical conveniences; they describe distributions of real outcomes across real histories. This removes the need for metaphysical hand-waving about non-existent possibilities influencing reality.
If physics is about describing reality, then relying on things that are, by construction, eternally non-existent to justify observed phenomena is conceptually incoherent. It is an attempt to have it both ways—to use abstract possibilities when convenient while denying their reality when inconvenient. That contradiction is why single-history frameworks ultimately fail to provide a satisfying foundation for probability and existence itself.
Quentin
--Le mar. 4 févr. 2025, 19:03, John Clark <johnk...@gmail.com> a écrit :
--
On Tue, Feb 4, 2025 at 12:56 PM 'spudb...@aol.com' via Everything List <everyth...@googlegroups.com> wrote:
> Bohmian mechanics v Everett-DeWiit-Wheeler?For Carroll, it probably means they're the same. Indistinguishable.
This is what I said about that about a month ago:
Pilot Wave Theory keeps Schrodinger's Equation but needs to add another entirely new very complicated equation called the Pilot Wave Equation that contains non-local variables. When an electron enters the two slit experiment the Pilot Wave in effect produces a little arrow pointing to one of the electrons with the caption under it saying "this is the real electron, ignore all the other ones". The Pilot Wave does absolutely nothing except erase unwanted universes, it is for this reason that some have called Pilot Wave theory the Many Worlds theory in denial.
The Pilot Wave is unique in another way, it can affect matter but matter cannot affect it, if it's real it would be the first time in the history of physics where an exception to Newton's credo that for every action there is a reaction; even after the object it is pointing to is destroyed the pilot wave continues on, although now it is pointing at nothing and has no further effect on anything in the universe. Also, nobody has ever been able to make a relativistic version of the Pilot Wave Equation.Paul dirac found a version of Schrodinger's Equation that was compatible with special relativity as early as 1927.
John K Clark See what's on my new list at Extropolis8b0
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups "Everything List" group.
To unsubscribe from this group and stop receiving emails from it, send an email to everything-li...@googlegroups.com.
To view this discussion visit https://groups.google.com/d/msgid/everything-list/CAJPayv3JL9f40jD-4qG0ry6z38ZtVysrh9RhE%2BDirJrSWzaX-w%40mail.gmail.com.
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups "Everything List" group.
To unsubscribe from this group and stop receiving emails from it, send an email to everything-li...@googlegroups.com.
To view this discussion visit https://groups.google.com/d/msgid/everything-list/CAMW2kAopDs_qGcSEgaZJdrDUu7qgMzWgvNbE4EPFgw5pxRBQcA%40mail.gmail.com.
--
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups "Everything List" group.
To unsubscribe from this group and stop receiving emails from it, send an email to everything-li...@googlegroups.com.
To view this discussion visit https://groups.google.com/d/msgid/everything-list/CAJPayv0sjJLK%3D1Pj4wPXET8YJaYRLSoHRwOqfs7ha1fviLYHhw%40mail.gmail.com.
To view this discussion visit https://groups.google.com/d/msgid/everything-list/ab8b9168-9459-476b-9b9b-930c6763289a%40gmail.com.
Brent,You say that unrealized possibilities are what probabilities quantify, but in a single-history framework, those possibilities never had any existence beyond the formalism. If only one history is real, then all other possibilities were never actually possible in any meaningful way—they were never real candidates for realization, just mathematical constructs. That’s not an emotive argument; it’s pointing out that the entire notion of probability in such a framework is detached from anything real.If probability is supposed to quantify real possibilities, then in a world where only one history exists for all eternity, what exactly is being quantified? If an event with a calculated probability of 50% never happens in this one history, then its true probability was always 0%. Your framework claims to allow for multiple possibilities, but in practice, it only ever realizes one, making the rest nothing more than empty labels.And you assert that alternatives have a "grounding in reality"—but what does that mean in a framework where they never actually happen? If they had a genuine grounding, they would have to be part of reality in some form, even if only probabilistically. But in a single-history framework, that never happens. The probabilities exist only in the mind of the observer, with no external ontological reality. They are tools that describe nothing but a retrospective justification of what already happened.The supposed "problem" in MWI—that all possibilities are realized—actually solves this issue. It gives probabilities a real basis in the structure of the universe rather than treating them as abstract bookkeeping. The probabilities describe real distributions across real histories rather than referring to things that were never real to begin with.The single-world view wants to use probability while simultaneously denying the existence of the things probability refers to. That’s not just emotive talk—it’s a contradiction at the foundation of the framework.Quentin
--
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups "Everything List" group.
To unsubscribe from this group and stop receiving emails from it, send an email to everything-li...@googlegroups.com.
To view this discussion visit https://groups.google.com/d/msgid/everything-list/CAFxXSLRi46%2B4v7Si6zFBSijV9FeKFdBS3YzydLTA5Txe7Qx%2BzA%40mail.gmail.com.
Repeated experiments don’t change the core issue. Even if you perform an experiment a trillion times, in a single-history universe, there is still only one realized sequence of outcomes. That means certain possibilities with greater than zero probability will simply never happen—not just in a given run, but ever.
--
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups "Everything List" group.
To unsubscribe from this group and stop receiving emails from it, send an email to everything-li...@googlegroups.com.
To view this discussion visit https://groups.google.com/d/msgid/everything-list/CAFxXSLQYoyNvJPy3-r3sAexKY5%3DmHQ1A9CTn6mA7o215Mf4DvQ%40mail.gmail.com.
If all possibilities were realized the wouldn't have probabilities assigned to them...exactly the problem that arises in MWI.
> The sequence of N repetitions gives you an estimate of the probability distribution.
> there is no interaction between branches and there is no causal link.
Brent,
You say that unrealized possibilities are what probabilities quantify, but in a single-history framework, those possibilities never had any existence beyond the formalism.
If only one history is real, then all other possibilities were never actually possible in any meaningful way—they were never real candidates for realization, just mathematical constructs. That’s not an emotive argument; it’s pointing out that the entire notion of probability in such a framework is detached from anything real.
If probability is supposed to quantify real possibilities, then in a world where only one history exists for all eternity, what exactly is being quantified? If an event with a calculated probability of 50% never happens in this one history, then its true probability was always 0%.
Your framework claims to allow for multiple possibilities, but in practice, it only ever realizes one, making the rest nothing more than empty labels.
And you assert that alternatives have a "grounding in reality"—but what does that mean in a framework where they never actually happen?
If they had a genuine grounding, they would have to be part of reality in some form, even if only probabilistically.
But in a single-history framework, that never happens. The probabilities exist only in the mind of the observer, with no external ontological reality. They are tools that describe nothing but a retrospective justification of what already happened.
The supposed "problem" in MWI—that all possibilities are realized—actually solves this issue. It gives probabilities a real basis in the structure of the universe rather than treating them as abstract bookkeeping.
The probabilities describe real distributions across real histories rather than referring to things that were never real to begin with.
To view this discussion visit https://groups.google.com/d/msgid/everything-list/CAMW2kAp7UGDVrCzGRnrucy%3DzYRUgOM0-o1X7Vhs1j6c5GVQygg%40mail.gmail.com.
To view this discussion visit https://groups.google.com/d/msgid/everything-list/23bf8e7f-645e-4f5e-a056-b3fc200a958c%40gmail.com.
Bruce,
That still doesn't address the core issue. If the universe has a unique history and a finite existence, then there is a fundamental limit to the number of repetitions that can ever occur. There is no guarantee that all possible outcomes will ever be realized, no matter how large N is. Some events with nonzero probability simply will never happen. That alone is enough to undermine frequentism in a single-history framework—it relies on the assumption that probabilities reflect long-run frequencies, but if the history is finite and unique, the necessary "long run" does not exist.
Even in an infinite universe, if history is still unique, there is no mechanism ensuring that all outcomes occur in proportions that match their theoretical probabilities.
Some possibilities with nonzero probability may remain unrealized forever, making their assigned probabilities meaningless in any real sense. They were never actual possibilities in the first place—just theoretical artifacts with no impact on reality.
Your argument assumes that probabilities describe reality in the single-world framework, but without an ensemble where all possibilities exist in some way, this assumption collapses.
--
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups "Everything List" group.
To unsubscribe from this group and stop receiving emails from it, send an email to everything-li...@googlegroups.com.
To view this discussion visit https://groups.google.com/d/msgid/everything-list/9575cf10-2b1e-4d42-a6e4-ee0992f757aa%40gmail.com.
Brent,I went through the document you sent, and it outlines the different interpretations of probability: mathematical, physical symmetry, degree of belief, and empirical frequency. But none of these resolve the core issue in a single-history universe—where probability is supposed to describe "possibilities" that, in the end, never had any reality.Your frequentist approach assumes that, given enough trials, outcomes will appear in proportions that match their theoretical probabilities. But in a finite, single-history universe, there is no guarantee that will ever happen. Some events with nonzero probability simply won’t occur—not because of statistical fluctuations, but because history only plays out one way. In that case, were those possibilities ever really possible? If something assigned a probability of 10% never happens in the actual course of the universe, then in what meaningful way was it ever a possibility?You argue that if all possibilities are realized, probability loses its meaning. But in a single-history world, probability is just as meaningless because it describes outcomes that never had a chance of being real. If probability is supposed to quantify potential realities, then in a framework where only one reality exists, probability is nothing more than a retrospective justification—it has no actual explanatory power.
--
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups "Everything List" group.
To unsubscribe from this group and stop receiving emails from it, send an email to everything-li...@googlegroups.com.
To view this discussion visit https://groups.google.com/d/msgid/everything-list/CAFxXSLRkqQMJMhHdKuSPdCngh6n%2B73by9XF4qT2FYw-R_vu41g%40mail.gmail.com.
Bruce,Quantum mechanics has explanatory power because it provides accurate predictions and a framework for modeling reality. The problem isn’t with quantum mechanics itself—it’s with trying to reconcile probability with a single-history universe where only one sequence of events ever occurs.In a framework where only one history unfolds, probability is purely descriptive—it does not explain why this history, rather than any other, is the one that exists. It assigns numbers to theoretical possibilities that never had a chance of being real. You keep asserting that probabilities are meaningful in a single-history view, but meaningful in what sense? If a certain event, despite being assigned a 30% probability, never happens in the one realized history, then in what sense was it ever a possibility?In contrast, in a framework where all possibilities are realized, probability maintains a clear meaning: it describes the relative measure of outcomes across the full set of realized possibilities. In that case, probability is tied to something real, rather than just being a tool we use to pretend that nonexistent possibilities matter.The fact that quantum mechanics works well does not mean that a single-history interpretation is logically coherent when it comes to probability. You’re conflating the success of QM with the philosophical implications of trying to force probability into a framework where unrealized possibilities never had any reality at all. That’s the problem you’re not addressing.
On Wednesday, February 5, 2025 at 1:36:55 PM UTC-7 Quentin Anciaux wrote:Brent,I went through the document you sent, and it outlines the different interpretations of probability: mathematical, physical symmetry, degree of belief, and empirical frequency. But none of these resolve the core issue in a single-history universe—where probability is supposed to describe "possibilities" that, in the end, never had any reality.Your frequentist approach assumes that, given enough trials, outcomes will appear in proportions that match their theoretical probabilities. But in a finite, single-history universe, there is no guarantee that will ever happen. Some events with nonzero probability simply won’t occur—not because of statistical fluctuations, but because history only plays out one way. In that case, were those possibilities ever really possible? If something assigned a probability of 10% never happens in the actual course of the universe, then in what meaningful way was it ever a possibility?You argue that if all possibilities are realized, probability loses its meaning. But in a single-history world, probability is just as meaningless because it describes outcomes that never had a chance of being real. If probability is supposed to quantify potential realities, then in a framework where only one reality exists, probability is nothing more than a retrospective justification—it has no actual explanatory power.The math remains internally consistent, but it becomes an empty formalism, detached from anything real. The whole structure relies on pretending that unrealized events still "exist" in some abstract sense, even though they never affect reality. That’s the contradiction at the heart of the single-history view. It uses probability to describe possibilities while simultaneously denying that those possibilities ever had a chance to be real.
Why do you assume that some non-zero probabilities never occur? How could you know this? Meanwhile, you prefer a theory, MIi, that can't be verified. Puzzling preferences. AG
--Le mer. 5 févr. 2025, 20:18, Brent Meeker <meeke...@gmail.com> a écrit :On 2/5/2025 2:54 AM, Quentin Anciaux wrote:
I recommend that you never play cards for money.Bruce,
That still doesn't address the core issue. If the universe has a unique history and a finite existence, then there is a fundamental limit to the number of repetitions that can ever occur. There is no guarantee that all possible outcomes will ever be realized, no matter how large N is. Some events with nonzero probability simply will never happen. That alone is enough to undermine frequentism in a single-history framework—it relies on the assumption that probabilities reflect long-run frequencies, but if the history is finite and unique, the necessary "long run" does not exist.
Yet they do match. QM is the most accurate, predictive theory there is.
Even in an infinite universe, if history is still unique, there is no mechanism ensuring that all outcomes occur in proportions that match their theoretical probabilities.
Where they all exist the probabilities (according to you) become 1, and "probability" is meaningless. I think you are just confused because you don't distinguish between the theory of probability and it's several different applications. You seem to think the world has to be only one certain way for it to apply. Try reading the attached.Some possibilities with nonzero probability may remain unrealized forever, making their assigned probabilities meaningless in any real sense. They were never actual possibilities in the first place—just theoretical artifacts with no impact on reality.
Your argument assumes that probabilities describe reality in the single-world framework, but without an ensemble where all possibilities exist in some way, this assumption collapses.
Brent
Probabilities become detached from what actually happens and instead become abstract formalism with no grounding in the real world. That’s the problem: the single-world view wants to use probability theory as if all possibilities have meaning while simultaneously denying that they do.
In contrast, in a framework where all possibilities are realized in different branches, probability retains its explanatory power. It describes actual distributions of outcomes rather than pretending that unrealized events still somehow "exist" in a purely mathematical sense. If the universe is unique, and history is unique, then probability has no true foundation—it’s just a game with numbers, untethered from what actually happens.
Quentin
--You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups "Everything List" group.
To unsubscribe from this group and stop receiving emails from it, send an email to everything-li...@googlegroups.com.To view this discussion visit https://groups.google.com/d/msgid/everything-list/9575cf10-2b1e-4d42-a6e4-ee0992f757aa%40gmail.com.
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups "Everything List" group.
To unsubscribe from this group and stop receiving emails from it, send an email to everything-li...@googlegroups.com.
To view this discussion visit https://groups.google.com/d/msgid/everything-list/cac56d63-3597-4bd2-b8a6-9f0410b08930n%40googlegroups.com.
Bruce,Quantum mechanics has explanatory power because it provides accurate predictions and a framework for modeling reality. The problem isn’t with quantum mechanics itself—it’s with trying to reconcile probability with a single-history universe where only one sequence of events ever occurs.In a framework where only one history unfolds, probability is purely descriptive—it does not explain why this history, rather than any other, is the one that exists.
It assigns numbers to theoretical possibilities that never had a chance of being real. You keep asserting that probabilities are meaningful in a single-history view, but meaningful in what sense? If a certain event, despite being assigned a 30% probability, never happens in the one realized history, then in what sense was it ever a possibility?
In contrast, in a framework where all possibilities are realized, probability maintains a clear meaning: it describes the relative measure of outcomes across the full set of realized possibilities. In that case, probability is tied to something real, rather than just being a tool we use to pretend that nonexistent possibilities matter.
--
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups "Everything List" group.
To unsubscribe from this group and stop receiving emails from it, send an email to everything-li...@googlegroups.com.
To view this discussion visit https://groups.google.com/d/msgid/everything-list/CAFxXSLQ_67BtMSZAFTjh0EYscnmAm8GVwuMMziM3exCDr-csag%40mail.gmail.com.
On Wednesday, February 5, 2025 at 1:36:55 PM UTC-7 Quentin Anciaux wrote:Brent,I went through the document you sent, and it outlines the different interpretations of probability: mathematical, physical symmetry, degree of belief, and empirical frequency. But none of these resolve the core issue in a single-history universe—where probability is supposed to describe "possibilities" that, in the end, never had any reality.Your frequentist approach assumes that, given enough trials, outcomes will appear in proportions that match their theoretical probabilities. But in a finite, single-history universe, there is no guarantee that will ever happen. Some events with nonzero probability simply won’t occur—not because of statistical fluctuations, but because history only plays out one way. In that case, were those possibilities ever really possible? If something assigned a probability of 10% never happens in the actual course of the universe, then in what meaningful way was it ever a possibility?You argue that if all possibilities are realized, probability loses its meaning. But in a single-history world, probability is just as meaningless because it describes outcomes that never had a chance of being real. If probability is supposed to quantify potential realities, then in a framework where only one reality exists, probability is nothing more than a retrospective justification—it has no actual explanatory power.The math remains internally consistent, but it becomes an empty formalism, detached from anything real. The whole structure relies on pretending that unrealized events still "exist" in some abstract sense, even though they never affect reality. That’s the contradiction at the heart of the single-history view. It uses probability to describe possibilities while simultaneously denying that those possibilities ever had a chance to be real.Why do you assume that some non-zero probabilities never occur? How could you know this? Meanwhile, you prefer a theory, MIi, that can't be verified. Puzzling preferences. AGAG,I assume that some nonzero probabilities never occur because, in a single-history universe with finite time and a unique trajectory, there is no guarantee that every possible outcome will ever be realized. If history unfolds in only one way, then there will inevitably be events assigned nonzero probability that simply never happen. That’s not an assumption—it’s an unavoidable consequence of having only one realized history.
Bruce,
You’re trying to reduce the issue to my supposed "difficulty" with randomness, but that’s not the point. The problem isn’t whether quantum events are random—it’s whether probability has a meaningful foundation in a single-history universe where only one sequence of events is ever realized.You keep appealing to repeated trials, but even with infinite repetitions, some events with nonzero probability will never occur in the one and only history that unfolds. That’s not a minor detail—that’s a fundamental contradiction in the way probability is treated in a single-world framework. If an event assigned a 30% probability never happens, then its "probability" was meaningless in any real sense. It was never a real possibility, just a number in an equation.
Now, regarding the Born rule: You claim that MWI contradicts it, but your argument assumes that every possible branch must exist in equal measure, which is not what MWI predicts. The structure of the wavefunction naturally leads to branches that reflect the Born probabilities because those branches are weighted according to the squared amplitudes.
It’s not about equal-counted branching—it’s about the distribution of measure across branches, which naturally results in Born-rule outcomes.
Your argument also ignores the fact that in a single-history universe, the Born rule is just an imposed rule with no deeper explanation. Why do probabilities follow this rule in a framework where only one history exists? What forces the realized history to match the expected distribution?
If probabilities are just random assignments with no deeper foundation, then their success in predicting experimental results is equally mysterious in a single-history view.MWI provides an actual mechanism for why the Born rule emerges: it follows from the structure of the wavefunction itself.
Your argument, on the other hand, assumes the Born rule as a brute fact without explaining why a single realized history should respect it in the first place. That’s not an explanation—it’s just asserting that the math works and ignoring the deeper implications.
--
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups "Everything List" group.
To unsubscribe from this group and stop receiving emails from it, send an email to everything-li...@googlegroups.com.
To view this discussion visit https://groups.google.com/d/msgid/everything-list/CAFxXSLRyhs2d7wCGSJNRxoc_-zr4bLUJvbT53UPHiyGpHRmeDw%40mail.gmail.com.
Bruce,
Let’s take your own argument about probability and push it to its logical conclusion. You said that if something with a 30% probability doesn’t happen in a given set of trials, that just means the prior probability estimate was wrong. Fine. Now, let’s apply that logic to a real-world scenario.Imagine an asteroid is heading toward Earth, and based on all available data, models predict it has an 80% probability of impact. Yet, somehow, it doesn’t hit. By your reasoning, this means that the 80% estimate must have been wrong—because in the single-history universe, only what actually happens matters. The probability was just a number assigned to something that never had any reality.
But this raises an obvious problem: what is probability even describing in a single-history framework? If probabilities are supposed to quantify real possibilities, yet some of them never happen despite high probability assignments, then those probabilities were meaningless from the start. The asteroid example makes it clear—if a highly probable event doesn’t occur, it wasn’t a real possibility in any meaningful sense. It was just a mathematical expectation that reality never fulfilled.
In a multiverse framework, this isn’t an issue because the probabilities describe actual distributions of events across different branches. There exist branches where the asteroid hits and others where it doesn’t, and the 80% probability corresponds to the fraction of branches where impact occurs. But in a single-history framework, that 80% was just an empty number—nothing ever "happened" with 80% likelihood because only one outcome was ever real.Your argument boils down to saying, "Probability theory tells us what we should expect, but if reality doesn’t match, then the prior probability was wrong." But this means probability has no independent explanatory power—it is just a bookkeeping trick that retroactively adjusts itself to match what already happened. That’s not an actual explanation of events; it’s just a way of pretending probability still means something when it clearly doesn’t in a single-history world.
So tell me: in a single-history universe, if the asteroid doesn’t hit despite an 80% probability, was it ever actually an 80% chance event? Or was that probability just an illusion, describing something that was never going to happen in the only history that exists?
Bruce,
Repeated experiments don’t change the core issue. Even if you perform an experiment a trillion times, in a single-history universe, there is still only one realized sequence of outcomes. That means certain possibilities with greater than zero probability will simply never happen—not just in a given run, but ever.
--
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups "Everything List" group.
To unsubscribe from this group and stop receiving emails from it, send an email to everything-li...@googlegroups.com.
To view this discussion visit https://groups.google.com/d/msgid/everything-list/CAFxXSLSFvd4UHR8yMaa%2BtkRdc5d7_X7edp1Vpez-1iyc5EkyPA%40mail.gmail.com.
--
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups "Everything List" group.
To unsubscribe from this group and stop receiving emails from it, send an email to everything-li...@googlegroups.com.
To view this discussion visit https://groups.google.com/d/msgid/everything-list/7859554a-525f-4639-abdc-0be2367b7935%40gmail.com.
Bruce,
You’re making a distinction between single-event probabilities and repeated trials, but you’re not addressing the core issue: in a single-history universe, probability is only ever descriptive, not explanatory. You claim that if an asteroid has an 80% chance of impact but doesn’t hit, then the 20% chance was simply realized. But this explanation is entirely retrospective—it tells us nothing about why this history, rather than any other, is the one that unfolded.
You say, "assuming the calculations were accurate, then there certainly was an 80% chance of hitting, and a 20% chance of missing." But in what sense was that 80% ever real? In the only history that exists, the asteroid never had an 80% chance of hitting—it always had a 100% chance of missing because that’s what happened. The probability was just a number assigned before the event, with no actual force in determining the outcome.
In a multiverse framework, probabilities are grounded in actual distributions across histories. The 80% means that in 80% of branches, the asteroid hits, and in 20%, it misses. This gives probability an explanatory role—it describes the structure of reality, not just an arbitrary number assigned to something that never had a chance of happening.
You claim that MWI has no way to connect probabilities to the wavefunction, but that’s false. The structure of the wavefunction naturally assigns measure to branches,
and those measures correspond to the squared amplitudes of the coefficients—the Born rule emerges from this structure.
You keep asserting that probabilities in MWI are meaningless because "all possibilities happen," but that’s only true if you ignore the fact that measure matters. Not all branches are weighted equally, and the frequencies of outcomes reflect those weights.
The issue isn’t whether we can calculate probabilities in a single-history world—it’s whether those probabilities have any real ontological meaning. You claim that in a single-history world, probabilities "just work," but that’s not an explanation. It’s just a way of pretending that numbers assigned before an event have some deeper reality when, in truth, they don’t. In the end, the only thing that exists is the one history that happens, and everything else was just an illusion of possibility.
On Tue, Feb 4, 2025 at 6:22 PM Brent Meeker <meeke...@gmail.com> wrote:
If all possibilities were realized the wouldn't have probabilities assigned to them...exactly the problem that arises in MWI.
You've forgotten that it's not just an electron that is a quantum object and thus part of the Universal Wave Function (UWF), you are also part of the UWF. There are an astronomical number of branches of the UWF, perhaps an infinite number, and those branches do not interact with each other and thus can be interpreted as separate "worlds".
You the observer are stuck in just one of those branches and thus lack sufficient information to know if you are in the branch where the cat is alive or the branch where the cat is dead, you need to open the box and look in to get that information, before that you do what you always do when you don't have enough information to be certain, you work with probabilities.
The quantum bomb tester demonstrates it is possible to obtain information about an object without interacting with it in any way, the bomb does explode in some branches (a.k.a. worlds) of the UWF but if you set things up properly you the observer will be in a branch where the bomb did NOT explode and yet you know for certain the bomb is working properly and will explode if it detects even one photon. Many Worlds can easily explain how interaction free measurement could work, and do so without invoking some sort of ill defined wave function collapse, by simply acknowledging that all outcomes occur each in its own independent branch of the UWF. But the competitors of Many Worlds struggle to give an intuitive explanation of how interaction free measurement could possibly work. And this is important!
Years ago in high school physics I was taught a derivation of Heisenberg's Uncertainty Principle that started from the assumption that you'd have to use photons to detect something and that would always disturb what you're looking at, but I now know that derivation was invalid; it got the right answer but for the wrong reason. The real reason is due to the mathematical structure of quantum mechanics, the uncertainty principle is derived from the non-commuting nature of observable operators, like position and momentum, or energy and time.
I've also heard the “using photons to detect something disturbs it” argument to explain why Maxwell's Demon does not violate the Second Law Of Thermodynamics,
On Wed, Feb 5, 2025 at 5:48 AM Bruce Kellett <bhkel...@gmail.com> wrote:> The sequence of N repetitions gives you an estimate of the probability distribution.OK, but even if N=1, such as when I flip a coin just once, I can still obtain a probability of it coming up heads that makes sense.
And the long-run relative frequency of an event occurring in repeated trials is just one way to define probability, you could also say it's the ratio of all possible favorable outcomes to all possible outcomes, or as a degree of belief based on available evidence that can be updated when new evidence becomes available.
Brent,
You're arguing that probabilities in a single-world framework are as real as those of observed events because they are derived from the same equations. But if only one history ever happens, then unrealized possibilities are just numbers in a calculation, not something that ever had a chance of being real.
But that's exactly wrong. They are in the calculation precisely because they did have a chance of being real. You keep leaning on "only one history happens". But the probabilities are for the individual events. The probability of a die landing : is 1/6 .
The theory predicts probabilities, but what actually occurs is just one unique sequence of events. The rest—no matter how formally predicted—never existed in any form beyond the equations.
You claim that this does not imply determinism, but the fact remains that only one history ever unfolds.
Whether the process is called "random" or not, in practical terms, there is no actual underlying ensemble of events
—there is just the one sequence that reality plays out. That makes probability, in this framework, purely descriptive of an imagined set of possibilities that never had any ontological status.
You say that unrealized events are "part of reality probabilistically," but what does that even mean when they never actually happen? If an event is assigned a 60% probability but never occurs in the only history that exists, then in what sense was it ever a real possibility?
It was just an abstract calculation with no actual link to reality.
You keep referring to long strings of experiments as if an infinite series of trials is guaranteed to sample all possibilities—but in a finite universe with a unique history, that is simply not true.
Your attempt to equate probability with other concepts like energy or entropy fails because those are directly observable and quantifiable properties of physical systems.
Probability, in a single-history framework, is not a property of the world—it’s a mental construct we impose on it. It’s not like energy or momentum; it’s a way of reasoning about things that will never actually exist.
MWI, on the other hand, does not set all probabilities to 1 arbitrarily.
It gives probability a real foundation by making it about relative frequencies across real histories.
There, probabilities describe distributions of actualized outcomes,
not abstract unrealized ones. In contrast, in a single-world view, probability is just a way of pretending that things that never existed somehow mattered. That is the contradiction you keep glossing over.
To view this discussion visit https://groups.google.com/d/msgid/everything-list/CAMW2kApBiR65jFriNpQ8mp4d2_p1k%3DWEr1QPBoS3fkDbkgTbPQ%40mail.gmail.com.
Brent,
I went through the document you sent, and it outlines the different interpretations of probability: mathematical, physical symmetry, degree of belief, and empirical frequency. But none of these resolve the core issue in a single-history universe—where probability is supposed to describe "possibilities" that, in the end, never had any reality.
Your frequentist approach assumes that, given enough trials, outcomes will appear in proportions that match their theoretical probabilities.
But in a finite, single-history universe, there is no guarantee that will ever happen.
Some events with nonzero probability simply won’t occur—not because of statistical fluctuations, but because history only plays out one way. In that case, were those possibilities ever really possible? If something assigned a probability of 10% never happens in the actual course of the universe, then in what meaningful way was it ever a possibility?
You argue that if all possibilities are realized, probability loses its meaning. But in a single-history world, probability is just as meaningless because it describes outcomes that never had a chance of being real.
If probability is supposed to quantify potential realities, then in a framework where only one reality exists, probability is nothing more than a retrospective justification—it has no actual explanatory power.
The math remains internally consistent, but it becomes an empty formalism, detached from anything real.
The whole structure relies on pretending that unrealized events still "exist" in some abstract sense,
--
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups "Everything List" group.
To unsubscribe from this group and stop receiving emails from it, send an email to everything-li...@googlegroups.com.
To view this discussion visit https://groups.google.com/d/msgid/everything-list/CAFxXSLSoueSm74SRU0nie_b%3D%3DCDft6rWboAJPMKfyNLUbHAhOA%40mail.gmail.com.
To view this discussion visit https://groups.google.com/d/msgid/everything-list/501201e8-75f0-4117-97b2-1c87ca805b86%40gmail.com.
--
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups "Everything List" group.
To unsubscribe from this group and stop receiving emails from it, send an email to everything-li...@googlegroups.com.
To view this discussion visit https://groups.google.com/d/msgid/everything-list/dd78e99d-0384-45e0-b072-4d820a3c53dc%40gmail.com.
>>> there is no interaction between branches and there is no causal link.>> True. And that is exactly why those independent branches of the Universal Wave Function can be thought of as independent worlds.> And why the MWI is unverifiable and tantamount to a fantasy. AG
> why do you postulate an infinite number of worlds?
> Are you claiming that there are no inherently probabilistic events, e.g. nuclear decay, and it's just a matter of ignorance?
> Single world theories also easily explain how "interaction free" measurements work.
> But Quentin is asserting that if it comes up heads then the probability of heads was 1 and the probability of tails was 0. Thus completely misapplying the concept of probability.>>> The sequence of N repetitions gives you an estimate of the probability distribution.>> OK, but even if N=1, such as when I flip a coin just once, I can still obtain a probability of it coming up heads that makes sense.
> Consider halting the defense of many histories and go on offense: What principle selects that singular outcome? What privileges it above all others and by what means/mechanism?
On Wed, Feb 5, 2025 at 8:21 PM Brent Meeker <meeke...@gmail.com> wrote:> why do you postulate an infinite number of worlds?As I've said many times before, I don't demand that and neither does Many Worlds, there might be an infinite number or there might only be an astronomical number to an astronomical power of them, Many Worlds is agnostic on that issue and so am I.
>> As I've said many times before, I don't demand that and neither does Many Worlds, there might be an infinite number or there might only be an astronomical number to an astronomical power of them, Many Worlds is agnostic on that issue and so am I.> IMO, the MWI does assume an infinite number of worlds, though that infinity might be only countable. You can easily infer that from the countably many energy states of the H atom. AG
> The Rydberg series for the H-atom is countably infinite. AG
Bruce,
You keep insisting that randomness "just is" and that no deeper explanation is possible, but that’s precisely the problem with the single-history view: it reduces probability to a descriptive afterthought with no fundamental meaning. You argue that in a single-history universe, we must simply accept that an event had an 80% chance of happening even if it never does.
But in what sense was that probability real if only one history ever unfolds and the event never occurs?
You say that probabilities are "real enough" because they are based on prior experience. But prior experience in a single-history universe is just another way of saying, "this is what happened before." That’s not an explanation; it’s circular reasoning.
You’re using past outcomes to justify probability assignments, but if probability is supposed to describe potential events, then what does it mean when a "possible" event never happens, despite being assigned a nonzero probability?
In a multiverse framework, probability describes the relative frequency of events across actualized branches.
It is not just an abstract expectation—it is grounded in the structure of the wavefunction itself.
You dismiss the idea that measure in the wavefunction corresponds to probability, but this is not an assumption—it follows naturally from the mathematics of quantum mechanics. The Born rule is not an extra assumption in MWI; it emerges from decision theory (Deutsch-Wallace), from symmetry arguments (Zurek’s envariance), or from self-locating uncertainty. You keep demanding "proof,"
yet you accept the Born rule as a brute fact in your own framework without any justification beyond "that’s just how quantum mechanics works."
Meanwhile, your single-history approach provides no mechanism for why probabilities match experimental results.
You claim that probability "just works" without explaining why the realized history should respect the Born distribution at all. You dismiss branch weighting in MWI as unproven, yet you offer no competing explanation for why a single sequence of events should follow probabilistic predictions.
Ultimately, your position amounts to: "Random events happen, probabilities just work, and there’s no deeper reason for anything."
That’s not an explanation—it’s an assertion that we shouldn’t ask questions. If you’re satisfied with that, fine, but let’s not pretend it’s a superior foundation for probability. It’s just giving up on understanding why reality follows probabilistic laws in the first place.
To view this discussion visit https://groups.google.com/d/msgid/everything-list/CAMW2kAoUzMipVLp0HwY%2BHXeDKDWhH988t9U6pMWne8%2BZmF3JRg%40mail.gmail.com.
Quentin, you are perhaps too generous to believe in discussion here. Consider halting the defense of many histories and go on offense: What principle selects that singular outcome? What privileges it above all others and by what means/mechanism? There is no coherent answer without invoking a god, a Brent, an Alan, Cosmin, Trump, Spud, Giulio, it just happens etc. who just proclaim it on some creation day - and it was good. Closet bible worshippers. Apologies, but the types of fallacious argument (ad verecundiam) they rely on, are the same, even if not regarding this exact proposition.
q4x
--
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups "Everything List" group.
To unsubscribe from this group and stop receiving emails from it, send an email to everything-li...@googlegroups.com.
To view this discussion visit https://groups.google.com/d/msgid/everything-list/CAJPayv2%3DD6Csgj0bTcnXytjfOf1jT6pF-hMf4QrAxH-ja02vVA%40mail.gmail.com.
To view this discussion visit https://groups.google.com/d/msgid/everything-list/583254b6-006c-47c6-8c60-b470d94b17f0%40gmail.com.
>> If AFTER I hit a golf ball 200 yards and we all see that it landed on one particular blade of grass and you ask what was the probability that it landed on that one particular blade the correct answer would be 100% despite the fact that there are millions of other blades of grass that it could've landed on.
> Depends on how the word "was" is meant. If "was" refers to before you hit the ball, then the probability was not 1.0. Even after it hit the ground and was rolling it was not 1. It only "was" 1 if "was" refers to now.
> Thus arbitrarily imposing a frequentist model on the world by imagining an ensemble of universes.
> This is really unecessary. It's just a sop to intuition.
> Why not accept that probabilities need not be frequencies?
> Did you not read my essay on the subject?
On Fri, Feb 7, 2025 at 5:28 PM Brent Meeker <meeke...@gmail.com> wrote:> Thus arbitrarily imposing a frequentist model on the world by imagining an ensemble of universes.Hugh Everett wasn't imagining, he was just taking seriously a prediction that Schrodinger's Equation makes; it's true that particular prediction can't be tested, but many other predictions that the equation makes can be and they've all passed with flying colors;
On Fri, Feb 7, 2025 at 5:28 PM Brent Meeker <meeke...@gmail.com> wrote:
> Thus arbitrarily imposing a frequentist model on the world by imagining an ensemble of universes.Hugh Everett wasn't imagining, he was just taking seriously a prediction that Schrodinger's Equation makes;
it's true that particular prediction can't be tested, but many other predictions that the equation makes can be and they've all passed with flying colors;
therefore I see no reason why your default condition should be to assume that other prediction is pure nonsense, especially given the fact that it can explain why the quantum world is so weird.
> This is really unecessary. It's just a sop to intuition.
I don't know what you mean by that. If you can find a logical reason to justify your intuition that is not a "sop", it is a profound revelation.
> Why not accept that probabilities need not be frequencies?
I do because you can't use that approach to assess the probability of a unique event, such as the probability that X will win the next election. The 4 meanings of the word "probability" that I mentioned, the ratio of favorable outcomes to all outcomes, the long run frequency of an event occurring, a degree of belief which can be updated when more information becomes available, and the square of the absolute value of a quantum wave function, are all valid and do not contradict each other; which one you use depends on the circumstances. However if you don't believe in Many Worlds then, although you know from experiment it works, it's very hard to understand why the square of the absolute value of a quantum wave function works and how it can have any sort of relationship with the three other meanings of the word "probability".And it's always true that no matter how you calculate a probability, if you obtain new information you may have to change that number. Monty Hall asks you to pick a door and there is only one chance in three that you will pick the one that has the prize behind it, but later when Monty opens a door that you did NOT pick and you can see that it did NOT have the prize behind and gives you a chance to change your original pick you do because now that you've obtained new information your chance of getting the price increases from 1/3 to 2/3.
> Did you not read my essay on the subject?
Yes and I couldn't find anything in it that was controversial, I agree with it; but I think you should have at least mentioned the square of the absolute value of a quantum wave function. I especially liked it when you said:
"So there are (at least) four ways to interpret a probability assignment"
--
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups "Everything List" group.
To unsubscribe from this group and stop receiving emails from it, send an email to everything-li...@googlegroups.com.
To view this discussion visit https://groups.google.com/d/msgid/everything-list/CAJPayv2zNnsE8NhyFrrMwsdJ_W%3DZcsdfyas4WWOU_cf7ziiqig%40mail.gmail.com.
> Which is a very peculiar way of doing empirical science.>>>Thus arbitrarily imposing a frequentist model on the world by imagining an ensemble of universes.>> Hugh Everett wasn't imagining, he was just taking seriously a prediction that Schrodinger's Equation makes;
> Schroedinger actually had the same problem with QM; he saw that "measurement" was not explained by the evolution of his equation.
>> it's true that particular prediction can't be tested, but many other predictions that the equation makes can be and they've all passed with flying colors;
> Neglecting the point that all those other worlds have no existence beyond showing up in mathematics as having a probability bigger than zero and less than one.
>> I see no reason why your default condition should be to assume that other prediction is pure nonsense, especially given the fact that it can explain why the quantum world is so weird.
> I don't consider it "pure nonsense".
> it doesn't actually explain the mechanism of worlds splitting, as evidenced by Sean Carroll's answer to the question whether the splitting is instantaneous across the universe or does it spread out in some way at the speed to light? He says, "It doesn't matter." So much for a better explanation.
> It doesn't indicate how the Born rule is implemented in the multiple worlds.
> Why doesn't your intuition just embrace probability and reflect that probability means some things happen and other things don't.
> When you get a poker hand, do imagine all possible poker hands were dealt in other worlds?
> not every probability is based on ignorance.
>> Hugh Everett wasn't imagining, he was just taking seriously a prediction that Schrodinger's Equation makes; it's true that particular prediction can't be tested, but many other predictions that the equation makes can be and they've all passed with flying colors;> And all other interpretations of QM have passed exactly the same tests with equally flying colours. Everett does not have a monopoly on truth.
On Sat, Feb 8, 2025 at 6:06 PM Brent Meeker <meeke...@gmail.com> wrote:> Which is a very peculiar way of doing empirical science.>>>Thus arbitrarily imposing a frequentist model on the world by imagining an ensemble of universes.>> Hugh Everett wasn't imagining, he was just taking seriously a prediction that Schrodinger's Equation makes;
That's not peculiar for empirical science at all. We can't detect virtual particles and we will never be able to, but physicists believe they exist because they can explain how the Casimir Effect works and why the electron has the magnetic moment that it has. And it's not just in quantum mechanics. We don't know if the entire universe is finite or infinite, or if it's open or closed, but either way we do know that the entire universe must be MUCH larger than the observable universe.If the universe is open then it has negative curvature, and thus it must be infinite because there cannot be an finite space with uniform negative curvature without introducing boundaries and or singularities.For a closed universe with a curvature of 0.4% (if it was larger than that we would've already detected it and we haven't), the radius of curvature would need to be AT LEAST 160 times larger than the observable universe's radius, which is 46.5 billion light years; 160 × 46.5 billion= a radius of 7.4 trillion light years , and the corresponding minimum volume of the entire universe would be 25,600 times the volume of the observable universe. And there's more. Although we can see galaxies that are now 46.5 billion light years away, if they are further away than 17 billion light years (corresponding to a time when the universe was about 500 million years old) and we aimed a beam of light at it, that light would NEVER reach the galaxy because relative to us space would be expanding faster than the speed of light.> Schroedinger actually had the same problem with QM; he saw that "measurement" was not explained by the evolution of his equation."Measurement" is not explained by Schrodinger's equation IF you assume that everything follows that equation EXCEPT for a thing called "the observer" which for some unknown reason obeys only classical physics.>> it's true that particular prediction can't be tested, but many other predictions that the equation makes can be and they've all passed with flying colors;
> Neglecting the point that all those other worlds have no existence beyond showing up in mathematics as having a probability bigger than zero and less than one.Paul Dirac thought the negative solutions that showed up in his equation had no existence beyond showing up in his mathematics, but he was wrong, it indicated the existence of antimatter. Dirac is later quoted as saying that his equation was smarter than he was.>> I see no reason why your default condition should be to assume that other prediction is pure nonsense, especially given the fact that it can explain why the quantum world is so weird.
> I don't consider it "pure nonsense".OK, I'm very glad to hear that!> it doesn't actually explain the mechanism of worlds splitting, as evidenced by Sean Carroll's answer to the question whether the splitting is instantaneous across the universe or does it spread out in some way at the speed to light? He says, "It doesn't matter." So much for a better explanation.Carroll is saying two things by that:1) It's impossible even in theory to ever determine the answer to that question.2) The answer to that question is not important, that is to say it makes no observable difference, and it's not even clear that the question makes sense.
On Sat, Feb 8, 2025 at 6:06 PM Brent Meeker <meeke...@gmail.com> wrote:> Which is a very peculiar way of doing empirical science.>>>Thus arbitrarily imposing a frequentist model on the world by imagining an ensemble of universes.>> Hugh Everett wasn't imagining, he was just taking seriously a prediction that Schrodinger's Equation makes;
That's not peculiar for empirical science at all. We can't detect virtual particles and we will never be able to, but physicists believe they exist because they can explain how the Casimir Effect works and why the electron has the magnetic moment that it has. And it's not just in quantum mechanics.
We don't know if the entire universe is finite or infinite, or if it's open or closed, but either way we do know that the entire universe must be MUCH larger than the observable universe.
If the universe is open then it has negative curvature, and thus it must be infinite because there cannot be an finite space with uniform negative curvature without introducing boundaries and or singularities.For a closed universe with a curvature of 0.4% (if it was larger than that we would've already detected it and we haven't), the radius of curvature would need to be AT LEAST 160 times larger than the observable universe's radius, which is 46.5 billion light years; 160 × 46.5 billion= a radius of 7.4 trillion light years , and the corresponding minimum volume of the entire universe would be 25,600 times the volume of the observable universe. And there's more. Although we can see galaxies that are now 46.5 billion light years away, if they are further away than 17 billion light years (corresponding to a time when the universe was about 500 million years old) and we aimed a beam of light at it, that light would NEVER reach the galaxy because relative to us space would be expanding faster than the speed of light.
> Schroedinger actually had the same problem with QM; he saw that "measurement" was not explained by the evolution of his equation.
"Measurement" is not explained by Schrodinger's equation IF you assume that everything follows that equation EXCEPT for a thing called "the observer" which for some unknown reason obeys only classical physics.
>> it's true that particular prediction can't be tested, but many other predictions that the equation makes can be and they've all passed with flying colors;
> Neglecting the point that all those other worlds have no existence beyond showing up in mathematics as having a probability bigger than zero and less than one.
Paul Dirac thought the negative solutions that showed up in his equation had no existence beyond showing up in his mathematics, but he was wrong, it indicated the existence of antimatter. Dirac is later quoted as saying that his equation was smarter than he was.
>> I see no reason why your default condition should be to assume that other prediction is pure nonsense, especially given the fact that it can explain why the quantum world is so weird.
> I don't consider it "pure nonsense".
OK, I'm very glad to hear that!
> it doesn't actually explain the mechanism of worlds splitting, as evidenced by Sean Carroll's answer to the question whether the splitting is instantaneous across the universe or does it spread out in some way at the speed to light? He says, "It doesn't matter." So much for a better explanation.
Carroll is saying two things by that:
1) It's impossible even in theory to ever determine the answer to that question.
2) The answer to that question is not important, that is to say it makes no observable difference, and it's not even clear that the question makes sense.
I believe both points are valid. Contrary to what some say, Einstein didn't prove the Luminiferous Aether didn't exist, he proved it wasn't important.> It doesn't indicate how the Born rule is implemented in the multiple worlds.
If there are multiple worlds then, until you open the box, you don't have enough information to be certain if you're in the world where the cat is alive or in the world where the cat is dead, so you would have to resort to probability; and if you're using Schrödinger's equation the Born Rule is the only way to make sure the number you get is between zero and one and all the probabilities add up to exactly one.
> Why doesn't your intuition just embrace probability and reflect that probability means some things happen and other things don't.
Because Schrodinger's equation is deterministic so "the atom just happens to decay" is an insufficient explanation.
And because if X and Y react with each other and then the result of that reaction reacts with Z, I get one end result if I observe the X and Y reaction and something completely different if I don't observe it. Give me an intuitive explanation of how that could be without using Many Worlds. And then give me an intuitive explanation of how interaction free measurement could work without using Many Worlds.
> When you get a poker hand, do imagine all possible poker hands were dealt in other worlds?
I could but in that particular case there are vastly simpler computational means I could use to obtain a useful probability. The situation would be very different if instead of cards you gave me a sealed box and I had to bet if there was a live or dead cat in it.> not every probability is based on ignorance.
I think at the deepest level every probability is based on ignorance because I think Many Worlds is correct and all that Many Worlds is saying is that Schrodinger's equation means what it says, and Schrodinger's equation is 100% deterministic. If I always knew what world I was in I would know if the cat was alive or dead before I opened the box and I wouldn't need to resort to probability for anything.
On Thu, Feb 06, 2025 at 11:38:52AM +1100, Bruce Kellett wrote:
>
> Many worlds theory does not have any comparable way of relating probabilities
> to the properties of the wave function. In fact, if all possibilities are
> realized on every trial, the majority of observers will get results that
> contradict the Born probabilities.
>
I'm not sure what you mean by "contradict", but the majority of
observers will get results that lie within one standard deviation of
the expected value (ie mean) according to the distribution of Born
probabilities. If this is what you mean by "contradict", then you are
trivially correct, but uninteresting. If you mean the above statement
is false according to the MWI, then I'd like to know why. It sure
doesn't seem so to me.
As JC says, we don't know if the number of observers is countably
infinite (which would be my guess), uncountably infinite or just plain
astronomically large. In any case, the proportion of observers seeing
results outside of one standard deviation is of measure zero for
practical purposes. If that is not the case, please explain.
> The other point is that the set of branches obtained in Everettian many worlds
> is independent of the amplitudes, or the Born probabilities for each outcome,
> so observations on any one branch cannot be used as evidence, either for or
> against the theory.
>
We've had this discussion before. They're not independent, because the
preparation of the experiment that defines the Born probabilities
filters the set of allowed branches from which we sample the
measurements.
> See the articles by Adrian Kent and David Albert in "Many Worlds: Everett,
> Quantum Theory, and Reality"(OUP, 2010) Edited by Saunders, Barrett, Kent, and
> Wallace.
>
I've already got a copy of Kent's paper in my reading stack. Albert's paper
appears to be behind a paywall, alas :(.
In any case, it'll be a while before I get to the paper - just
wondering if you had a 2 minute explanation of the argument. What I've
heard so far on this list hasn't been particularly convincing.
> As JC says, we don't know if the number of observers is countably
> infinite (which would be my guess), uncountably infinite or just plain
> astronomically large. In any case, the proportion of observers seeing
> results outside of one standard deviation is of measure zero for
> practical purposes. If that is not the case, please explain.
>
>
> The number of anomalous results in MWI is not of measure zero in any realistic
> case.
>
I'm trying to see why you say that.
> > The other point is that the set of branches obtained in Everettian many worlds
> > is independent of the amplitudes, or the Born probabilities for each outcome,
> > so observations on any one branch cannot be used as evidence, either for or
> > against the theory.
> >
>
> We've had this discussion before. They're not independent, because the
> preparation of the experiment that defines the Born probabilities
> filters the set of allowed branches from which we sample the
> measurements.
>
>
> I don't know what this means.
>
In preparing the experiment, you are already filtering out the
observers who choose to observe something different. And that
definitely changes the set of worlds, or branches under
consideration. So you cannot say (as you did) "the set of branches
obtained in Everettian many worlds is independent of the
amplitudes". Whether the set of branches changes in precisely the way
to recover the Born rule is a different question, of course, and
obviously rather hard to prove.
> > See the articles by Adrian Kent and David Albert in "Many Worlds: Everett,
> > Quantum Theory, and Reality"(OUP, 2010) Edited by Saunders, Barrett, Kent, and
> > Wallace.
> >
>
> I've already got a copy of Kent's paper in my reading stack. Albert's paper
> appears to be behind a paywall, alas :(.
>
> In any case, it'll be a while before I get to the paper - just
> wondering if you had a 2 minute explanation of the argument. What I've
> heard so far on this list hasn't been particularly convincing.
>
>
> A quote from Kent (p. 326 of the book)
> " After N trials, the multiverse contains 2^N branches, corresponding to all N
> possible binary string outcomes. The inhabitants on a string with pN zero and
> (1-p)N one outcomes will, with a degree of confidence that tends towards one as
> N gets large, tend to conclude that the weight p is attached to zero outcomes
> branches and weight (1-p) is attached to one outcome branches. In other words,
> everyone, no matter what outcome string they see, tends towards complete
> confidence in the belief that the relative frequencies they observe represent
> the weights."
That is true. And the observers observing something like an all zero
sequence, or alternating 1s and 0s, are living in what we called a
"wabbity universe" some years ago on this list. Those observers become
vanishingly small as N→∞ in the space of all observers.
I'm still not convinced there is a problem here...
On Mon, Feb 10, 2025 at 11:35:11AM +1100, Bruce Kellett wrote:
> On Mon, Feb 10, 2025 at 10:52 AM Russell Standish <li...@hpcoders.com.au>
> wrote:
>
>
> > On Mon, Feb 10, 2025 at 09:25:57AM +1100, Bruce Kellett wrote:
> > > On Mon, Feb 10, 2025 at 8:49 AM Russell Standish
Yes - the decision to set the apparatus at angle θ filters the set of
observers to those who make the same choice. And that filtering makes
a difference in this case.
I'll read Kent's paper to see if he makes the same error.
--
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups "Everything List" group.
To unsubscribe from this group and stop receiving emails from it, send an email to everything-li...@googlegroups.com.
To view this discussion visit https://groups.google.com/d/msgid/everything-list/CAFxXSLRbPrij2JN1%3DugeBTQou9Kwvvd%2Bk%3Dd8pxFbVH19SX57DQ%40mail.gmail.com.
Bruce,Yes, every possible experience is lived by some version of me in MWI, but that does not mean all experiences are equally likely or subjectively equivalent. The measure of a branch determines how many copies of me experience a given outcome. In practice, my conscious experience will overwhelmingly be shaped by the branches with higher measure, not by the rare and improbable ones.
For example, if a quantum event has a 1% probability, then there will be branches where I observe it, but they will be exponentially fewer than those where I do not. The measure is not just an abstract number—it reflects the relative weight of different outcomes in the wavefunction. This is why, as an observer, I will almost always see frequencies matching the Born rule, because the majority of my copies exist in branches where this distribution holds.
Your argument assumes that since all branches exist, they must be equiprobable, but this ignores the fact that measure determines how many copies of an observer exist in each branch. In a lottery, every ticket exists, but some are printed in larger quantities. Saying "all branches exist, so they must be equal" is as flawed as saying "all lottery tickets exist, so all should win equally."Ultimately, my conscious experience is not determined by the mere existence of branches, but by the relative number of copies of me in each. Low-measure branches do exist, but they are not representative of my experience. This is why MWI naturally leads to the Born probabilities, without assuming collapse or introducing an arbitrary rule.Your reasoning collapses probability into mere branch-counting, but probability is about where observers actually find themselves, not about an abstract collection of sequences.
--
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups "Everything List" group.
To unsubscribe from this group and stop receiving emails from it, send an email to everything-li...@googlegroups.com.
To view this discussion visit https://groups.google.com/d/msgid/everything-list/CAFxXSLQshEssmB9vHes%2B7foaotfY08EDBdGTcfw7Ot78SUgBHQ%40mail.gmail.com.
>> That's not peculiar for empirical science at all. We can't detect virtual particles and we will never be able to, but physicists believe they exist because they can explain how the Casimir Effect works and why the electron has the magnetic moment that it has. And it's not just in quantum mechanics.
> Virtual particles are just a mathematical tool to form infinite sums in a consistent way. No physicist believes they exist.
>> We don't know if the entire universe is finite or infinite, or if it's open or closed, but either way we do know that the entire universe must be MUCH larger than the observable universe.
>So what?
>> Schrodinger's equation is deterministic so "the atom just happens to decay" is an insufficient explanation.
> But all MWI does is push the insufficiency off to "you just happen to be in the world where the atom decayed at 3:10pm"
>> I think at the deepest level every probability is based on ignorance because I think Many Worlds is correct and all that Many Worlds is saying is that Schrodinger's equation means what it says, and Schrodinger's equation is 100% deterministic. If I always knew what world I was in I would know if the cat was alive or dead before I opened the box and I wouldn't need to resort to probability for anything.
> I think you think MWI is correct simply because you don't know of any alternatives.
> A lot of other physicists, like me, think MWI is no better than Copenhagen. It just pushes the problem off to more obscure questions, like how does the orthgonality of worlds spread?
> And why isn't Zeh's Darwinian decoherence enough?
> I think you think MWI is correct simply because you don't know of any alternatives.
Guilty as charged. I've said more than once that Many Worlds is the least bad explanation for quantum weirdness that I know of, if somebody comes up with something better I'll drop it like a hot potato.
> So did you read any of the papers I cited?>>> I think you think MWI is correct simply because you don't know of any alternatives.
>>Guilty as charged. I've said more than once that Many Worlds is the least bad explanation for quantum weirdness that I know of, if somebody comes up with something better I'll drop it like a hot potato.
--
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups "Everything List" group.
To unsubscribe from this group and stop receiving emails from it, send an email to everything-li...@googlegroups.com.
To view this discussion visit https://groups.google.com/d/msgid/everything-list/CAJPayv3sN%2BFSX9J5%3D_NJYtxVr1Rm0Okt_4BJZR88CEPs7CsinQ%40mail.gmail.com.
Bruce,
Your argument assumes that all measurement sequences are equally likely, which is false in MWI. The issue is not about which sequences exist (they all do) but about how measure is distributed among them. The Born rule does not emerge from simple branch counting—it emerges from the relative measure assigned to each branch.
You claim that in large N trials, most sequences will have an equal number of zeros and ones, implying that the estimated probability will tend toward 0.5. But this ignores that the wavefunction does not generate sequences with uniform measure. The amplitude of each sequence is determined by the product of individual amplitudes along the sequence, and when you apply the Born rule iteratively, high-measure sequences dominate the observer’s experience.Your mistake is treating measurement as though every sequence has equal likelihood, which contradicts the actual evolution of the wavefunction. Yes, there are 2^N branches, but those branches do not carry equal measure. The vast majority of measure is concentrated in the sequences that match the Born distribution, meaning that nearly all observers find themselves in worlds where outcomes obey the expected frequencies.This is not speculation; it follows directly from the structure of the wavefunction. The weight of a branch is not just a number—it represents the relative frequency with which observers find themselves in different sequences. The fact that a branch exists does not mean it has equal relevance to an observer's experience.Your logic would apply if MWI simply stated that all sequences exist and are equally likely. But that is not what MWI says. It says that the measure of a branch determines the number of observer instances that experience that branch. The overwhelming majority of those instances will observe the Born rule, not because of "branch counting," but because high-measure sequences contain exponentially more copies of any given observer.If your argument were correct, QM would be falsified every time we ran an experiment, because we would never observe Born-rule statistics.
Yet every experiment confirms the Born rule, which means your assumption that "all sequences contribute equally" is demonstrably false.
You are ignoring that measure, not count, determines what observers experience.
Bruce,
Your argument assumes that all measurement sequences are equally likely, which is false in MWI. The issue is not about which sequences exist (they all do) but about how measure is distributed among them. The Born rule does not emerge from simple branch counting—it emerges from the relative measure assigned to each branch.
You claim that in large N trials, most sequences will have an equal number of zeros and ones, implying that the estimated probability will tend toward 0.5. But this ignores that the wavefunction does not generate sequences with uniform measure. The amplitude of each sequence is determined by the product of individual amplitudes along the sequence, and when you apply the Born rule iteratively, high-measure sequences dominate the observer’s experience.
Your mistake is treating measurement as though every sequence has equal likelihood, which contradicts the actual evolution of the wavefunction. Yes, there are 2^N branches, but those branches do not carry equal measure.
The vast majority of measure is concentrated in the sequences that match the Born distribution, meaning that nearly all observers find themselves in worlds where outcomes obey the expected frequencies.
This is not speculation; it follows directly from the structure of the wavefunction. The weight of a branch is not just a number—it represents the relative frequency with which observers find themselves in different sequences. The fact that a branch exists does not mean it has equal relevance to an observer's experience.
Your logic would apply if MWI simply stated that all sequences exist and are equally likely. But that is not what MWI says. It says that the measure of a branch determines the number of observer instances that experience that branch. The overwhelming majority of those instances will observe the Born rule, not because of "branch counting," but because high-measure sequences contain exponentially more copies of any given observer.
If your argument were correct, QM would be falsified every time we ran an experiment, because we would never observe Born-rule statistics.
--
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups "Everything List" group.
To unsubscribe from this group and stop receiving emails from it, send an email to everything-li...@googlegroups.com.
To view this discussion visit https://groups.google.com/d/msgid/everything-list/CAFxXSLS518CcE8Wuj3FHe_66hnGN-KZFb%2BwOJ7-cHC_geo1N_w%40mail.gmail.com.
Your argument is based on treating the measurement process as merely counting sequences of zeros and ones, while dismissing the amplitudes as “just numbers.” But this ignores that the wavefunction governs the evolution of the system, and the amplitudes are not arbitrary labels—they encode the structure of reality. The Schrodinger equation evolves the system deterministically, and when measurement occurs, the measure of each branch determines how many observer instances find themselves in it.
You claim that the amplitude of a sequence does not affect what is measured, yet this is exactly what determines how many observers experience a given sequence.
The claim that “you do not ever see the amplitude” misses the point: you do not directly observe measure, but you observe its consequences. The reason we see Born-rule statistics is that the measure dictates the relative number of observers experiencing different sequences.
Le lun. 10 févr. 2025, 23:21, Bruce Kellett <bhkel...@gmail.com> a écrit :
On Mon, Feb 10, 2025 at 11:09 PM Quentin Anciaux <allc...@gmail.com> wrote:
Bruce,
Your argument assumes that all measurement sequences are equally likely, which is false in MWI. The issue is not about which sequences exist (they all do) but about how measure is distributed among them. The Born rule does not emerge from simple branch counting—it emerges from the relative measure assigned to each branch.
You really are obsessed with the idea that I am assuming that all measurement sequences are equally likely. It does not matter how many times I deny this, and point out how my argument does not depend in any way on such an assumption, you keep insisting that that is my error. I think you should pay more attention to what I am saying and not so much to your own prejudices.
Each of the binary sequences that result from N trials of measurements on a 2-component system will exist independently of the original amplitudes. For example, the sequence with r zeros, and (N - r) ones, will have a coefficient a^r b^(N-r). You are interpreting this as a weight or probability without any evidence for such an interpretation. If you impose the Born rule, it is the Born probability of that sequence. But we have not imposed the Born rule, so as far as I am concerned it is just a number. And this number is the same for that sequence whenever it occurs. The point is that I simply count the zeros (and/or ones) in each sequence. This gives an estimate of the probability of getting a zero (or one in that sequence). That estimate is p = r/N. Now that probability estimate is the same for every occurrence of that sequence. In particular, the probability estimate is independent of the Born probability from the initial state, which is simply a^2.
The problem here is that we get all possible values of the probability estimate p = r/N from the set of 2^ binary sequences that arise from every set of N trials. This should give rise to concern, because only very few of these probability estimates are going to agree with the Born probability a^2. You cannot, at this stage, use the amplitudes of each sequence to downweight anomalous results because the Born rule is not available to you from the Schrodinger equation.
The problem is multiplied when you consider that the amplitudes in the original state |psi> = a|0> + b|1> are arbitrary, so the true Born probabilities can take on any value between 0 and 1. This arbitrariness is not reflected in the set of 2^N binary sequences that you obtain in any experiment with N trials because you get the same set for any value of the original amplitudes
You claim that in large N trials, most sequences will have an equal number of zeros and ones, implying that the estimated probability will tend toward 0.5. But this ignores that the wavefunction does not generate sequences with uniform measure. The amplitude of each sequence is determined by the product of individual amplitudes along the sequence, and when you apply the Born rule iteratively, high-measure sequences dominate the observer’s experience.
Your mistake is treating measurement as though every sequence has equal likelihood, which contradicts the actual evolution of the wavefunction. Yes, there are 2^N branches, but those branches do not carry equal measure. The vast majority of measure is concentrated in the sequences that match the Born distribution, meaning that nearly all observers find themselves in worlds where outcomes obey the expected frequencies.
This is not speculation; it follows directly from the structure of the wavefunction. The weight of a branch is not just a number—it represents the relative frequency with which observers find themselves in different sequences. The fact that a branch exists does not mean it has equal relevance to an observer's experience.
Your logic would apply if MWI simply stated that all sequences exist and are equally likely. But that is not what MWI says. It says that the measure of a branch determines the number of observer instances that experience that branch. The overwhelming majority of those instances will observe the Born rule, not because of "branch counting," but because high-measure sequences contain exponentially more copies of any given observer.
If your argument were correct, QM would be falsified every time we ran an experiment, because we would never observe Born-rule statistics.
That is the point I am making. MWI is disconfirmed by every experiment. QM remains intact, it is your many worlds interpretation that fails.
Yet every experiment confirms the Born rule, which means your assumption that "all sequences contribute equally" is demonstrably false.
Since I do not make that assumption, your conclusion is wrong.
You are ignoring that measure, not count, determines what observers experience.
When you do an experiment measuring the spin projection of some 2-component state, all that you record is a sequence of zeros and ones, with r zeros and (N - r) ones. You do not ever see the amplitude of that sequence. It has no effect on what you measure, so claiming that it can up- or down-weight your results is absurd.
Bruce
Your argument is based on treating the measurement process as merely counting sequences of zeros and ones, while dismissing the amplitudes as “just numbers.”
But this ignores that the wavefunction governs the evolution of the system, and the amplitudes are not arbitrary labels—they encode the structure of reality.
The Schrodinger equation evolves the system deterministically, and when measurement occurs, the measure of each branch determines how many observer instances find themselves in it.
You claim that the amplitude of a sequence does not affect what is measured, yet this is exactly what determines how many observers experience a given sequence. The claim that “you do not ever see the amplitude” misses the point: you do not directly observe measure, but you observe its consequences. The reason we see Born-rule statistics is that the measure dictates the relative number of observers experiencing different sequences.
Your argument suggests that since measure is not directly observable, it cannot influence what we experience. But this is incorrect for the same reason that probability distributions matter in classical systems:
You cannot observe probability itself, only its consequences over many trials.
In a biased coin flip (90% heads, 10% tails), every sequence of flips exists in MWI.
But most copies of an observer will find themselves in sequences where heads appear 90% of the time.
The fact that all sequences exist does not mean they contribute equally to an observer’s experience.
--
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups "Everything List" group.
To unsubscribe from this group and stop receiving emails from it, send an email to everything-li...@googlegroups.com.
To view this discussion visit https://groups.google.com/d/msgid/everything-list/CAFxXSLSnE0YvUR3SqKZZwPsGyzxOvaXRk3CHoSk52M3qSMq_GQ%40mail.gmail.com.
Bruce,Your argument assumes that all branches are equally weighted in terms of observer experience, which contradicts what we actually see in quantum experiments. The claim that the Schrödinger equation is "insensitive" to amplitudes is incorrect. The amplitudes evolve deterministically under the Schrödinger equation and define the measure associated with each outcome. The Born rule does not need to be "inserted" into MWI—it emerges naturally if one considers measure as determining how many observer instances experience each outcome.Your claim that there are exactly 2^N observers after N trials and that each one "counts equally" ignores what measure represents. The fundamental point is that not all branches contribute equally to what an observer experiences. Yes, an observer exists on every branch, but that does not mean they exist in equal numbers.In standard probability theory, an event occurring in more instances is simply more likely to be observed. Similarly, in MWI:A branch with a higher amplitude means there are exponentially more copies of the observer experiencing that outcome.
This is not "assigning degrees of existence"—it is stating that measure determines how many versions of an observer find themselves in a given sequence.You can call this "silly," but it's the only way MWI remains consistent with experiments. If each observer counted equally across all branches, we would expect uniform probabilities, contradicting the Born rule.
The Schrödinger equation is not "insensitive" to amplitudes; it governs their evolution. The amplitudes define how much of the total wavefunction exists in each outcome. Saying that amplitudes are "inert" is like saying that in classical probability, event frequencies are "inert" because the probability distribution does not dynamically change per trial.
The fact that amplitudes don’t directly affect local observations does not mean they are irrelevant. You do not need to "see" probability distributions to experience their effects. In classical cases, you observe probabilities through frequency distributions—not because you see an abstract probability function floating in space.
Similarly, in MWI, you experience the effects of amplitude-based measure because the majority of your copies exist in branches that follow the Born rule.
Your argument frames measure as a metaphysical claim about "degrees of existence," but that’s a strawman. Measure is not about some observers being "more real" than others—it’s about how many instances of a given observer exist in different branches.
Imagine a lottery where some numbers are printed millions of times and others are printed once. Saying "each ticket exists, so all are equal" ignores the fact that you are overwhelmingly more likely to pick a ticket that was printed millions of times.This is exactly what happens in MWI:Yes, every sequence of outcomes exists.But observers overwhelmingly find themselves in high-measure sequences because there are simply more instances of them there.
If your claim were correct, quantum mechanics would fail to match experiment, because the observed frequencies would not match the Born rule. Since that never happens, the conclusion is clear: measure, not naive branch counting, determines what observers experience.
Yes, there is currently no clear cut theories to recover the born rule from Schrödinger equation alone, doesn’t mean there aren't.
Also I'm not an advocate of MWI per se, I prefer information theory approach from which we should be able to recover MW like theories and a measure (maybe mixing some UD and speed prior)
--
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups "Everything List" group.
To unsubscribe from this group and stop receiving emails from it, send an email to everything-li...@googlegroups.com.
To view this discussion visit https://groups.google.com/d/msgid/everything-list/CAFxXSLT705r0mBnnxsXzgAHLatyCF%2BKTjRbkZgR9HOFKN3vbwQ%40mail.gmail.com.
> The Schrodinger equation is completely insensitive to the amplitudes. They are just carried along as inert parameters.
> the Born rule, and probability interpretations per se, are not in the Schrodinger equation.
> According to MWI there is a branch for every possible value, and the observer splits along with the branching, so there is an observer on every branch. After N trials of the binary case, there are 2^N branches, with an observer (copy of the original experimenter) on every branch. These all exist equally, so your idea of weighting the branches according to the amplitudes makes no sense: there can be no "degrees of existence". All the observers exist equally, so all are equally entitled to count zeros to get an estimate of the underlying probability.
Bruce,
I'll still give it a try to get a discussion (dumb me).If your response boils down to "this is nonsense" and "you’re not clever enough," then you’re not engaging with the actual argument. The question is not whether the Schrödinger equation explicitly encodes the Born rule—it does not, just as it does not encode classical probability either. The question is whether MWI can recover the Born rule without adding collapse, and there are multiple serious approaches to doing so.Your claim that "MWI does not match experiments because it cannot get the Born rule" is just an assertion. The Schrödinger equation does evolve amplitudes, and those amplitudes do determine the structure of the wavefunction. You dismiss measure as meaningless, yet every quantum experiment confirms that the statistics follow . If naive branch counting were correct, experiments would contradict the Born rule—but they do not. That means something in MWI must account for it.Saying "all branches exist equally" ignores what "equally" even means in a probabilistic context. Probability is not about "some things happen while others don’t"—that’s a description, not an explanation. Classical probability arises because there are more ways for some outcomes to occur than others. In MWI, the weight of a branch is not a degree of existence—it’s a statement about how many copies of an observer find themselves in that outcome.If you have a counterargument, provide one—just dismissing the approach as "fantasy" without addressing the core point doesn’t make your position stronger. If you want to argue that MWI cannot recover the Born rule, then you need to explain why all proposed derivations (Deutsch-Wallace, Zurek’s envariance, self-locating uncertainty, etc.) are fundamentally flawed, not just assert that they don’t count.
--
You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups "Everything List" group.
To unsubscribe from this group and stop receiving emails from it, send an email to everything-li...@googlegroups.com.
To view this discussion visit https://groups.google.com/d/msgid/everything-list/CAFxXSLR50MgHVjm91s%3Dnz5urL98RSLGAC6FANmj23OMQbjOBXg%40mail.gmail.com.